Fredrik Westerlund's "Heidegger and the Problem of
Phenomena" provides a comprehensive analysis of Heidegger's evolving
engagement with the phenomenological method inherited from Husserl,
particularly focusing on the concept of phenomena. The study unfolds in three
parts, each tracing Heidegger's shifting perspectives on phenomena. The first
part scrutinizes Heidegger's early Freiburg lectures, highlighting the call for
a heightened sensitivity to the pretheoretical, existential aspects of lived
experience. The second part delves into the emergence of Heidegger's
fundamental ontology, culminating in "Being and Time", informed by an
acute awareness of human finitude, historicity, and the interplay with
Dilthey's hermeneutics and the Aristotelian inquiry into being. The third part
probes Heidegger's later works, where attention shifts from Dasein's
receptivity to meaning to the "history of being" itself, emphasizing
the dynamic of the event (Ereignis) that allows meaningful presence to be
encountered. Westerlund concludes the study with a detailed epilogue, offering
independent critical reflections on the implications of Heidegger's radical
historicism for ethical normativity and truth.
Westerlund's work stands in line with classical
phenomenological studies on Heidegger, placing it alongside renowned scholars
such as William J. Richardson, Steven Crowell, Daniel Dahlstrom, Burt Hopkins,
and Dermot Moran. Noteworthy is the meticulous attention given to Heidegger's
early lectures, distinguishing this study and drawing parallels with Theodore
Kisiel's seminal work on the genesis of "Being and Time."
Westerlund's analysis navigates the entire corpus of Heidegger's oeuvre,
unveiling a fundamental tension between the classical Husserlian
phenomenological approach and Heidegger's evolving "radical
historicism." This tension underlies Heidegger's dual identity as both
Husserl's prominent disciple and the figure central to the
hermeneutic-deconstructive tradition.
In the final section, Westerlund engages in a dual critique
of Heidegger's historicization of meaningfulness. Ethically, he aligns with
Levinas in asserting that Heidegger's prioritization of ontology over ethics
neglects the infinite moral imperative embodied in the face of the other.
Westerlund advocates for a universal ethics of love, emphasizing that the call
to love and care for the other transcends historical values and norms. He
contends that Heidegger's historicism overlooks the fundamental openness to the
call of the other person, which forms an irreducible source of moral meaning.
In terms of epistemology, Westerlund challenges Heidegger's contextualization
of truth, asserting that our experience of phenomena is fundamentally directed
towards realities that surpass our historical concepts. He argues that our
conceptual preunderstanding does not rigidly determine the scope of meaningful
experience.
In the culmination of his assessment, Westerlund contends
that Heidegger's endeavor to supplant intuition-based phenomenology with
historical reflection is ultimately destined to fall short. According to
Westerlund, Heidegger's transformation of phenomenology into a historical mode
of thought represents, in essence, a repudiation of phenomenology itself. He
posits that the deconstructive logic embraced by later Heidegger and his followers,
including Derrida, carries an inherent self-defeating quality, as it ultimately
relies on some transhistorical principle of meaning-constitution, be it the
Heideggerian event of Ereignis or the Derridean concept of différance.
Westerlund contends that whenever we attempt to fathom the human experience, we
invariably align ourselves with the phenomenological agenda of seeking
foundational and universally applicable first-personal experiences. In sum,
Westerlund suggests, "My suggestion is that in so far as philosophy takes
as its task to understand our experience of ethical-existential significance it
must primarily take the form of phenomenology"
The meticulousness and depth of Westerlund's exegetical
scholarship, especially his thorough examination of Heidegger's early lecture
courses spanning approximately 50 pages, is commendable. Westerlund largely
aligns with prevailing approaches and interpretations in Anglo-American
Heidegger research. However, there are certain points within this consensus that
might be open to scrutiny. For instance, the established translation of
Eigentlichkeit, a term denoting Dasein's awareness of the ontologically
fundamental structure of its existence as finite, situated, and characterized
by the three-dimensional flow of its temporality, as "authenticity"
could be challenged. Westerlund's discussion of authenticity stems from and
closely relates to a broader ethical emphasis. Like Levinas, Westerlund is
concerned about what he perceives as the "egoism" and lack of altruism
implied in Heidegger's portrayal of Dasein as existing for the sake of its own
potentialities. An alternative approach might involve recognizing that,
regardless of how selflessly and fervently I may be concerned for my fellow
human beings, I remain incapable of orienting my existence toward their finite
possibilities, simply because those possibilities are not mine. I may be
capable of selflessly sacrificing myself for someone, but I cannot experience
their death as my own. The singular temporal space allotted to me by my birth
and death is uniquely my responsibility. This fundamental existential reality
does not preclude caring for others, as Westerlund suggests, and it might be
argued that Heidegger, in fact, underscores a form of ethics centered on self-responsibility,
akin to Michel Foucault's exploration of an ethics of "self-care" in
Hellenistic philosophy.
Westerlund's bold attempt to grapple with Heidegger's later
thought, while more limited in scope compared to the extensive discussion of
the early lecture courses, is commendable. His insights on Heidegger's
"turn" in the 1930s, the dynamic of Ereignis, and the fundamental
role of the fourfold are, for the most
part, highly laudable. However, I would challenge Westerlund's hesitance to
categorize the later Heidegger as "phenomenological," despite
Heidegger's own insistence to the contrary. Since Westerlund steadfastly
defines phenomenology in terms of Husserl's emphasis on immediate intuitive
access to meaningful givenness, it is perhaps unsurprising that Heidegger's
characterization of his own thinking, particularly in his final 1973 seminar,
as a "phenomenology of the inapparent"—a phenomenology focused on the
implicit conditions of phenomenality, on the background context of meaningful
presence or accessibility that is not immediately phenomenally accessible or
present—fails to persuade Westerlund.
The question that arises here, in alignment with Heidegger,
concerns the extent to which "phenomenological" thinking can be
exhaustively defined within the parameters of Husserl's understanding of the
term. To what degree, and according to what criteria, has the overarching
project of Western philosophy not been inherently "phenomenological"?
That is, an endeavor to elucidate the possibility and structures of the
meaningful givenness of things, and our capacity to access them as meaningful
through experience and thought. Westerlund places significant emphasis on
"concrete phenomenological descriptions," that is, specific analyses
of particular types of phenomena in terms of their first-personal meaningful
phenomenality. Nevertheless, it could be argued that, as philosophy,
phenomenology—much like all philosophy—essentially grapples not with this or
that phenomenon or category of phenomenon, but with the structures and
conditions of phenomenality itself, with the very accessibility and
intelligibility of things. This is ultimately with the meaningful being of
beings, where specific concrete descriptions may no longer suffice.
Nonetheless, we will still be compelled to articulate our thoughts through
concepts, and these concepts will inevitably draw, to some extent, from our
background historical tradition.
Westerlund also dismisses Heidegger's effort, particularly
in "The End of Philosophy and the Task of Thinking" (1964) and other
late texts, to historically contextualize and situate Husserl's philosophical
project. However, it is widely acknowledged that Husserl's project initially
emerged as a response to a specific historical context—the ascent of antiphilosophical
naturalism, particularly in the form of logical psychologism. According to its
own self-understanding, Husserlian phenomenology sought to recover and salvage
a form of "first philosophy" in order to prevent philosophy from
devolving into a mere servant of natural science. Furthermore, Husserl saw
himself as carrying forward the legacy of modern philosophical classics—the
post-Cartesian emphasis on self-conscious subjectivity and the post-Kantian
transcendental endeavor. In characterizing his own position as
"transcendental idealism" and rejecting the Kantian notion of
things-in-themselves, Husserl, often without explicit acknowledgment, comes
remarkably close to certain positions advanced by the German idealists, such as
Fichte, Hegel, and Schelling, as the later Heidegger repeatedly suggests. Thus,
it might not be in Husserl's best interest to refuse acknowledgment that, like
all philosophers, he grappled with questions and issues within a specific
historical juncture, addressing these through concepts that were historically
constituted and imbued with significance
What distinguishes Westerlund's work, above all, from a
majority of Heidegger scholarship is his courageous stance in asserting an
independent philosophical position that is openly critical of Heidegger. To
fully honor this exceptional autonomy, I would like to conclude with some brief
questions and remarks that primarily pertain to the foundational tenets of
Westerlund's philosophy and are, in themselves, largely separate from his interpretation
of Heidegger.
Initially, Westerlund advocates for a universal ethics of
love, expressed in unequivocal and robust terms: "My claim is that the
personal address of the other and the possibility of loving her is there in
every historical situation—that is, regardless of the values and norms that
happen to govern my society and my identity". Moreover, he asserts,
"we are always already open to the understanding that all people,
universally and without exception, claim our love and care". However, an
opposing argument that readily comes to mind challenges the moral imperative of
loving all human beings as persons, without exception. It posits that this
imperative arises within a specific historical normative context, primarily
that of Christian ethics. Additionally, there is the inherent ambiguity of the
term "love" itself. The notion of love that Westerlund seems to work
with here is evidently not the Greek erōs, denoting erotic desire and pursuit,
nor philia, signifying affectionate attachment, but rather agapē, meaning
charity or selfless benevolence—a concept predominantly used in ancient Greece
to denote the love felt for immediate family members. It only expanded into the
universal ethical injunction of "loving one's neighbor" within the
context of Christian ethical teachings that advocate treating one's entire
community as an extended family. If love, in the sense of such
non-particularistic goodwill, genuinely transcends historical context, why is
this concept conspicuously absent from the ethics of pre-Christian antiquity?
Is the potential of this ethical concept to serve as a universal foundation for
all ethics not somewhat diminished by its emergence from a very specific
historical backdrop? Although many might argue otherwise, it remains challenging
to assert that this notion of ethics is universally and transhistorically
intuited.
The broader question at hand pertains to the very essence of
"ethics." Levinas' charge of prioritizing ontology over ethics, a
stance he attributes to Heidegger, is heavily contingent on a Kantian notion of
an ethics rooted in duty, in universally binding moral principles that render
ethics a matter of the will rather than of knowledge. This perspective
ultimately traces back to a theological ethics centered on divine command. In
the Aristotelian framework of knowledge, ethics was synonymous with ontology—a
localized ontological examination of active human life, specifically of the
"good life" in the sense of a life that optimally realizes humanity
and most fully actualizes human potential. As many scholars have pointed out,
including Volpi (1994), numerous aspects of Heidegger's "Being and
Time" draw inspiration from Aristotle's "Nicomachean Ethics,"
thereby characterizing fundamental ontology as an "ethics" in this
classical sense.
These historical observations shed light on a fundamental
challenge in Westerlund's intuition-based epistemic realism: its reluctance to
grapple seriously with the notion that our "immediate" intuitions
themselves bear the imprint of historical constitution. The ethical framework
proposed by Westerlund, rooted in love and aligned with the wider Levinasian
ethical perspective, is undeniably compelling. It resonates with many
contemporary ethical intuitions. However, it becomes apparent that these
intuitions are not uniformly held by all human beings across all eras. Instead,
they seem to have been deeply ingrained into the Western intellectual tradition
by its specific historical lineage, which encompasses two millennia of
Christian thought and two centuries of Kantian and post-Kantian thought.
Westerlund asserts that "our concepts [...] offer
themselves to us as possibilities to grasp or misinterpret matters that we
experience irrespective of these concepts" . Nevertheless, philosophers since
Plato have tended to take seriously the idea that we perceive matters as
specific, determinate entities through the mediation of concepts. With the aid
of concepts, we identify them as the distinct entities they are. Concepts are
typically seen as the means by which we articulate and categorize reality into
identifiable and discrete units or objects. Without them, reality might appear
as an indeterminate, sensuous chaos lacking in permanence—a state akin to
Heraclitean flux.
For a significant portion of philosophy's history, the
conceptual framework of reality was perceived as fixed and universally
applicable, as evident in Platonic and Hegelian dialectics. It is only in the
modern era that Western thought has gradually come to accept that different linguistic
and cultural systems possess fundamentally distinct and mutually incomparable
conceptual frameworks. For instance, according to the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis of
linguistic relativity, even though the visible spectrum of color detected by
the human eye remains more or less consistent across individuals, this spectrum
can be divided into discrete colors in a practically limitless number of ways.
Moreover, the quantity of color terms employed varies greatly based on
linguistic and cultural context. It is not incorrect to assert that different
cultures "perceive" as many colors as they distinguish through
specific terms. This example vividly illustrates the extent to which our most
elementary and primal intuitions—our immediate perceptions of color—are articulated
and constituted by concepts that, in turn, rely on cultural context.
The recognition of the embeddedness of concepts within
historically evolving natural languages coincided with an understanding of the
historical situatedness of meaningful experience. Heidegger, as well as
contemporary poststructuralism, inherit this Romantic tradition. While there
exist valid grounds for critiquing this tradition and its overall approach,
whether from a phenomenological perspective or otherwise, its principal insights
cannot be summarily dismissed as irrelevant.
No comments:
Post a Comment