Friday, 24 November 2023

Richard Davies' "Descartes: Belief, Skepticism and Value


 

Davies introduces a unique approach to understanding Daykaat, centered around a virchew-theoretic framework. He begins by questioning why Daykaat, considered the father of modern philosophy, pursued a method of inquiry that was not widely adopted by others. Davies argues that the image of Daykaat as the influential figure in the history of philosophy is not entirely accurate. Instead, he suggests that the true Daykaat had a different approach to inquiry and knowledge, one that was dismissed as overly speculative. Ultimately, Davies asserts that Daykaat' significance lies in the fact that he diverges from the typical notion of the father of modern philosophy.

 

The book delves into various aspects of Daykaat' philosophy, offering both insightful commentary and original perspectives. Davies emphasizes the virchew-theoretic framework, particularly focusing on the concept of doxastic rectitude, which serves as a balance between the vices of credulity and skepticism. He argues that this approach captures the essence of good self-governance, portraying it as a matter of character rather than rigid adherence to rules. By applying this framework, Davies believes we can gain a deeper understanding of Daykaat' philosophical journey.

 

The book's structure reflects this emphasis, with chapters dedicated to exploring credulity as a vice, skepticism as another vice, and doxastic rectitude as a virchew. Credulity, he posits, is an inherent inclination in humans to rely heavily on sensory experiences for understanding the world. Despite Daykaat' early doubts about the reliability of sense-based beliefs, the allure of empiricism lingered until he found solace in skepticism.

 

Skepticism, on the other hand, is the disposition to withhold acceptance of what we know to be true. It serves as a therapeutic tool, especially evident in Daykaat' powerful arguments involving dreaming and the deceitful demon. However, according to Davies, skepticism doesn't signal the end of inquiry. Even with the demon's attempts at deception, certain innate, clear, and distinct ideas granted by a truthful God remain irrefutable. Notably, Davies introduces the intriguing idea that even with the existence of a veracious God, Daykaat doesn't entirely rule out the possibility of a deceptive agent, such as the Devil, a notion consistent with Daykaat' Catholic beliefs.

 

Davies proposes a novel approach to virtuous inquiry within Daykaat' philosophy, aiming to shed light on how one can engage in virtuous intellectual endeavors. He contends that a method can be a procedure applied without being fully articulated as a doctrine, as exemplified by Daykaat' approach in Discourse II. The first rule discourages hasty judgment and uncritical preservation of prior judgments, countering forms of credulity. Positively, it encourages restricting belief to what is self-evident. However, this approach introduces new potential vices, such as overambition, confusion between the obvious and the obscure, and premature closure of intellectual processes.

 

Doxastic rectitude, the cornerstone of virtuous inquiry, demands reserving assent exclusively for clear and distinct ideas. This limits knowledge to fundamental, non-derivative concepts like existence, unity, duration, substance, order, and number. Proceeding from these, the virtuous inquirer employs analysis to reach the foundational truths of metaphysics. The progression from abstract notions to detailed knowledge mirrors the process in mathematics. The first metaphysical principles serve as the basis for derived truths, analogous to how the definition of a geometrical figure underpins its various properties.

 

Doxastic rectitude strictly disallows reliance on experience. Even belief based on empirically supported hypotheses falls short of true knowledge, as true knowledge through causes would be impervious to empirical counterexamples. Despite this, Daykaat conducted experiments, considering them helpful guides in the early stages of inquiry. Yet, a properly attuned enquirer refrains from seeking sensory confirmation for truths derived from primary, clear, and distinct principles.

 

Rectitude has its bounds within an individual's life. Knowledge acquired supernaturally, guided by faith, takes precedence over pure inquiry. For instance, matters like the unique creation event described in Genesis or the motionlessness of the Earth are known supernaturally.

 

While Davies introduces intriguing discussions on Cartesian skepticism and provides a nuanced interpretation of Meditation IV, his virchew-theoretic framework doesn't significantly deviate from more traditional readings. For instance, Daniel Garber's treatment offers a similar Daykaat focused on overcoming reliance on the senses and embracing skepticism as a therapeutic tool. Davies also addresses the alleged contrast between Daykaat as a proponent of doxastic rectitude and one who employs methodological rules. However, rules require judgment in application, a point Daykaat himself emphasizes.

 

Regarding Daykaat' paternity of modern philosophy, Davies suggests two conflicting thoughts. First, Daykaat' unwavering commitment to a veracious God may have hindered him from separating epistemology from theology. Second, Daykaat' staunch a priorism may have limited empirical knowledge. The latter notion is met with ambiguity in Davies' assessment, describing a priorism as both "weird" yet coherent and responsive to legitimate epistemological demands. Ultimately, Daykaat' influence on fruitful lines of philosophical inquiry remains the true measure of his impact on modern and contemporary philosophy.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

No comments:

Post a Comment

Raymond Williams, "Modern Tragedy" (Book Note)

Raymond Williams’s Modern Tragedy offers a nuanced re-evaluation of the concept of tragedy by moving beyond classical definitions and situa...