Sunday 18 February 2024

Althusser's " Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses (Notes towards an Investigation)" (Summary)

 

As Marx famously articulated, it is a fundamental truth that a society must continuously reproduce the conditions necessary for production alongside the act of production itself, or it would not be sustainable even for a year. The essence of production lies in the reproduction of these conditions, whether in a straightforward manner by maintaining the existing conditions or by expanding them. For now, let's set aside the nuances of this distinction. So, what does it mean to reproduce the conditions of production?

 

This question delves into a realm that is both deeply familiar and yet often overlooked. The seemingly self-evident truths, rooted in the perspective solely of production or even in practical productive activities themselves  are so ingrained in our everyday consciousness that it becomes exceedingly difficult, if not nearly impossible, to shift our perspective to that of reproduction. However, without this shift, everything remains abstract, and even distorted, particularly when considering production and, even more so, practical activities.

 

To simplify, let's assume that every society arises from a dominant mode of production. In this context, the process of production engages the available productive forces within specific relations of production.

 

Consequently, for a society to continue existing, it must simultaneously reproduce the conditions necessary for its production while engaging in the act of production itself. This entails the reproduction of:

 

The productive forces.

The existing relations of production.

2

Reproduction of the means of Production

 

It is now acknowledged, including by bourgeois economists whose focus lies in national accounting or modern macroeconomic theory, that Marx convincingly demonstrated in Capital Volume 2 that production must allow for the reproduction of the material conditions necessary for production itself—namely, the means of production.

 

The typical economist, much like the typical capitalist, understands the importance of annually forecasting the requirements for replacing what has been depleted or worn out in the process of production: raw materials, fixed assets (such as buildings), production equipment (machinery), and so forth. This perspective essentially mirrors the viewpoint of the firm, which tends to regard commentary on its financial accounting practices as sufficient.

 

However, the groundbreaking insights of Quesnay, who initially posed this crucial issue, and Marx, who provided a resolution, have illuminated that the reproduction of material production conditions cannot be adequately grasped at the level of the individual firm. This is because it doesn't manifest at that level within its actual conditions. What occurs at the firm level is merely an effect, providing only a glimpse into the necessity of reproduction while failing to reveal its underlying conditions and mechanisms.

 

A moment of reflection suffices to understand this: Consider Mr. X, a capitalist operating a spinning mill producing woolen yarn. He must indeed "reproduce" his raw materials, machinery, and so forth. However, he doesn't produce these elements for his own use—other capitalists do. For instance, an Australian sheep farmer, Mr. Y, or a heavy engineer manufacturing machine tools, Mr. Z, fulfill this role, and so on ad infinitum. Mr. Y and Mr. Z, in turn, must reproduce the conditions of their own production to enable the production of the goods essential for Mr. X's reproduction of production conditions. This chain extends indefinitely, ensuring that demand for means of production (for reproduction) can be met by supply on both national and global markets.

 

To understand this intricate mechanism, which resembles an "endless chain," one must adopt Marx's comprehensive approach and delve into the study of capital circulation relations between Department I (responsible for producing means of production) and Department II (responsible for producing means of consumption), as well as the realization of surplus value, as expounded in Capital Volumes 2 and 3.

 

While we won't delve into a detailed analysis of this matter here, it's crucial to acknowledge the imperative of reproducing material production conditions.

3

Reproduction of Labour-power

However, one crucial aspect we haven't addressed yet is the reproduction of the productive forces, specifically the reproduction of labor-power. This is distinct from the reproduction of the means of production.

 

From our examination of firm operations, particularly through the lens of financial accounting practices that account for depreciation and investment, we've gained a rough understanding of the material process of reproduction. However, we're now entering a realm where observation within the firm is, if not entirely blind, largely obscured. This is because the reproduction of labor-power predominantly occurs outside the firm's boundaries.

 

How is the reproduction of labor-power ensured? It's achieved by providing labor-power with the necessary material means for its own reproduction—namely, through wages. While wages are indeed included in the accounting of each enterprise, they are categorized as 'wage capital' and not explicitly recognized as a condition for the material reproduction of labor-power.

 

However, in practice, wages represent only the portion of the value produced by the expenditure of labor-power that is essential for its reproduction. This includes covering the costs of housing, food, clothing—essentially enabling the wage earner to return to the workplace each day, along with supporting the upbringing and education of children, who represent the future labor-power of the proletariat.

 

It's important to note that this value necessary for the reproduction of labor-power isn't solely determined by a 'biological' minimum wage but also by historical factors. Marx observed that the specific needs of workers vary historically, influenced by cultural and social factors.

 

Furthermore, this minimum wage is not merely defined by the historical needs recognized by the capitalist class but is rather shaped by the historical demands imposed by the proletarian class struggle. This struggle encompasses efforts to resist the lengthening of the working day and to combat reductions in wages.

 

However, ensuring the material conditions for the reproduction of labor-power isn't enough to guarantee its reproduction as labor-power. Labor-power must also possess the necessary competencies to function within the complex system of the production process. The development of productive forces and the specific unity characteristic of these forces at any given time necessitate that labor-power be skilled accordingly, tailored to meet the requirements of the socio-technical division of labor and its various roles and positions.

 

In capitalist societies, unlike those characterized by slavery or serfdom, the reproduction of labor-power's skills increasingly occurs outside of the production process itself. This is achieved primarily through the capitalist education system and other institutions.

 

What do children learn in school? While the specifics vary, they typically acquire fundamental skills such as reading, writing, and arithmetic, along with other elements of scientific or literary culture. These skills directly contribute to different roles in production, with varying levels of instruction provided for manual workers, technicians, engineers, and higher management. In essence, they acquire the necessary 'know-how' required for their future roles in the workforce.

In addition to acquiring technical skills and knowledge, children at school also learn the norms of behavior expected within the division of labor, tailored to the roles they are destined to fulfill. This includes moral, civic, and professional standards, which essentially translate into respect for the socio-technical division of labor and, ultimately, adherence to the order established by class domination. They are taught to speak in the appropriate manner, to interact with workers correctly, and, for future capitalists and their associates, to issue commands effectively. Essentially, they are trained to uphold the ruling ideology and, for those in positions of exploitation and repression, to manipulate it adeptly to maintain the domination of the ruling class.

 

To put it more precisely, the reproduction of labor-power necessitates not only the transmission of skills but also the perpetuation of submission to the established order—a reproduction of adherence to the ruling ideology for workers and a reproduction of the ability to manipulate this ideology effectively for exploiters and oppressors. All individuals involved in production, exploitation, and repression, not to mention the ideologists themselves, must be indoctrinated in this ideology to carry out their roles diligently.

 

Thus, the reproduction of labor-power hinges not just on the perpetuation of skills but also on the perpetuation of ideological subjection or the adept practice of the ruling ideology. It's important to recognize that ideological subjection is integral to the reproduction of labor-power.

 

This acknowledgment unveils the significant presence of a new reality: ideology.

 

Now, two comments follow from this discussion:

 

Firstly, I've provided a brief overview of the forms of reproducing productive forces—the means of production and labor-power. However, I have yet to address the reproduction of production relations, a crucial aspect of Marxist theory concerning the mode of production. To overlook this would be both a theoretical oversight and a grave political error, so I will delve into this topic. But before doing so, I must embark on another lengthy digression to obtain the necessary means for this discussion.

 

Secondly, in order to undertake this detour, I must revisit an old question: What defines a society?

4

II BASE AND SUPERSTRU C TURE

On several occasions, I have emphasized the revolutionary aspect of the Marxist conception of the 'social whole,' which is distinct from Hegel's notion of 'totality.' As I've reiterated (echoing well-known tenets of historical materialism), Marx envisioned the structure of every society as comprising 'levels' or 'instances' interconnected by a specific determinant: the economic base (the 'unity' of productive forces and relations of production) and the superstructure, which encompasses the politico-legal (law and the state) and ideological realms (comprising various ideologies such as religious, ethical, legal, and political ideologies).

 

Beyond its theoretical significance in distinguishing Marx from Hegel, this representation holds a crucial theoretical advantage: it enables the incorporation of what I've termed the respective indices of effectivity into essential concepts. But what does this mean exactly?

 

Consider this representation of society as an edifice with a base (infrastructure) supporting the superstructure's two 'floors.' This is a metaphor—a spatial one, to be precise—wherein the base's determination in the last instance by the economic base is emphasized. The metaphor serves to attribute an index of effectivity to the base, famously known as the determination in the last instance, which dictates the events in the upper 'floors' (of the superstructure) based on economic conditions. Consequently, the 'floors' of the superstructure possess varying indices of effectivity, determined by their relation to the economic base.

 

These 'floors' are not determinants in the last instance but are instead determined by the base's effectivity. While they may exhibit a relative autonomy, they are ultimately shaped by the base. This recognition leads to the acknowledgment of two key aspects within the Marxist tradition: the relative autonomy of the superstructure and the reciprocal action of the superstructure on the base.

 

The primary advantage of this Marxist topography lies in its revelation of the crucial role of determination (or effectivity) and its insistence that the base ultimately determines the entire edifice. However, the metaphorical nature of this representation—its descriptive quality—poses a significant limitation.

 

I now propose that it's both possible and necessary to approach things differently, without rejecting the classical metaphor outright but rather by moving beyond it to achieve a deeper understanding. By adopting the viewpoint of reproduction, many questions implied by the edifice metaphor but left unanswered can be illuminated.

 

My fundamental thesis is that these questions—particularly those pertaining to the superstructure—can only be adequately addressed from the perspective of reproduction. I will provide a brief analysis of law, the state, and ideology from this viewpoint, revealing insights from both the realms of practice and production and those of reproduction.

 

III THE STATE

The Marxist tradition is unequivocal on the nature of the state: as outlined in the Communist Manifesto and the Eighteenth Brumaire (and reiterated in subsequent classical texts, particularly Marx's writings on the Paris Commune and Lenin's State and Revolution), the state is explicitly viewed as a repressive apparatus. It serves as a 'machine' of repression that enables the ruling classes—whether bourgeois or big landowners—to maintain their dominance over the working class, facilitating the extraction of surplus-value, i.e., capitalist exploitation.

 

In essence, the state apparatus encompasses not only specialized entities like the police, courts, and prisons but also the military, which intervenes directly as a supplementary force in instances where the police are overwhelmed. At its zenith sits the head of state, the government, and the administration.

 

This Marxist-Leninist perspective hits upon a crucial point: the state, primarily characterized as a force of repressive execution and intervention in favor of the ruling classes in their struggle against the proletariat, embodies its basic function.

 

However, even in presenting the nature of the state in this manner, the analysis remains somewhat descriptive. I've previously discussed the concept of 'descriptive theory' to clarify that it represents an initial phase in theory development. While it is an essential starting point, it requires advancement beyond mere description.

 

Returning to our focus on the state, the descriptive theory provides a solid foundation for understanding its essence. This descriptive phase is correct in that it effectively correlates numerous observable facts—ranging from historical events like the June 1848 massacres to more subtle forms of domination—with the concept of the state as a class state embodied in the repressive state apparatus.

 

Yet, the descriptive theory alone does not suffice for the development of a comprehensive scientific theory of the state. While it offers a means of identifying instances of oppression and relating them to the state, it can also lead to a kind of static understanding—an acceptance of the apparent truth without delving deeper into the mechanisms at play.

 

To progress beyond this descriptive phase and gain a more profound understanding of the state's mechanisms, it's necessary to augment the classical definition of the state as a state apparatus.

 

5

The essentials of the Marxist theory of the state

 

First and foremost, it's crucial to clarify a fundamental point: the state, as manifested in its apparatus, holds significance solely in its function of wielding state power. The entirety of political class struggle revolves around the contestation of state power—its acquisition, retention, and consolidation—by a particular class or a coalition of classes. This distinction compels us to differentiate between state power (the attainment or maintenance of state power) and the state apparatus.

 

We've observed that the state apparatus can endure, even amidst political upheavals like bourgeois revolutions or coups d'état, without undergoing substantial alteration. Political events may affect the possession of state power while leaving the state apparatus largely intact. Even following a social revolution such as the one in 1917, a significant portion of the state apparatus persisted after the proletariat and the small peasantry seized state power—an observation emphasized by Lenin.

 

This distinction between state power and state apparatus is a fundamental aspect of the 'Marxist theory' of the state, which has been explicitly present since Marx's writings such as The Eighteenth Brumaire and Class Struggles in France. To summarize this theory:

 

The state is identified with its repressive apparatus.

State power and state apparatus are distinct entities.

The objective of class struggle revolves around the attainment of state power, leading to the utilization of the state apparatus by the ruling classes or their alliances to further their class interests.

The proletariat must seize state power to dismantle the existing bourgeois state apparatus and, initially, replace it with a proletarian state apparatus. Subsequently, a radical process ensues, aiming at the abolition of the state altogether.

While these principles are integral to the Marxist theory of the state, I contend that they still possess descriptive elements. Even with the proposed addition, this theory remains somewhat descriptive. However, it now encompasses more intricate and differential components whose functioning and impact necessitate further theoretical development.

 

The Ideological State Apparatuses

Thus, to augment the 'Marxist theory' of the state, we need to introduce another dimension, a terrain that the Marxist classics engaged with in their practical endeavors but did not fully systematize into theoretical form. This dimension extends beyond the distinction between state power and the state apparatus and involves a reality that aligns with the (repressive) state apparatus but differs from it significantly. I will refer to this reality by its conceptual term: the Ideological State Apparatuses (ISAs).

 

What exactly are the Ideological State Apparatuses? It's essential to distinguish them from the (repressive) state apparatus. In Marxist theory, the state apparatus encompasses entities like the government, administration, army, police, courts, and prisons, collectively constituting what I'll henceforth term the Repressive State Apparatus. The term "repressive" suggests that this apparatus functions through coercion, albeit ultimately, as repression may take non-physical forms such as administrative measures.

 

On the other hand, Ideological State Apparatuses manifest as distinct and specialized institutions readily observable by the immediate observer. Below is an empirical list of these ISAs, subject to detailed examination, testing, correction, and reorganization:

 

Religious ISA (comprising various churches and religious institutions)

Educational ISA (encompassing both public and private schools)

Family ISA

Legal ISA

Political ISA (encompassing political systems and parties)

Trade Union ISA

Communications ISA (encompassing press, radio, television, etc.)

Cultural ISA (encompassing literature, arts, sports, etc.)

It's vital to emphasize that the ISAs should not be confused with the (Repressive) State Apparatus. Several distinctions elucidate this difference:

 

Firstly, while there exists a single (Repressive) State Apparatus, there's a plurality of Ideological State Apparatuses. The unity that underpins this plurality of ISAs as a collective entity is not immediately apparent.

 

Secondly, whereas the (Repressive) State Apparatus predominantly operates within the public domain, a substantial portion of the Ideological State Apparatuses, despite their apparent dispersal, belongs to the private domain. Entities like churches, political parties, trade unions, families, certain schools, most newspapers, and cultural enterprises fall under the private domain.

Let's delve deeper into the distinction between Ideological State Apparatuses (ISAs) and the (Repressive) State Apparatus. While the Repressive State Apparatus operates predominantly through coercion, the ISAs function mainly through ideology, with secondary involvement in repression.

 

Some may question the classification of private institutions as ISAs, but this distinction is essential. Gramsci highlighted that the public-private dichotomy is a construct of bourgeois law, irrelevant to the state's domain, which transcends such distinctions. Similarly, whether an institution is public or private matters less than how it functions. Private entities can effectively serve as ISAs, as demonstrated by a thorough analysis of any ISA.

 

Crucially, both state apparatuses operate through a combination of violence and ideology. However, the (Repressive) State Apparatus primarily relies on repression, while the ISAs predominantly function through ideology, employing repression secondarily, albeit in subtle and often concealed ways.

 

The unity among diverse ISAs lies in their shared functioning through ideology, albeit beneath the ruling ideology, which reflects the interests of the ruling class. Despite their contradictions, ISAs ultimately serve to reproduce the ruling ideology. The ruling class, which wields state power, also influences ISAs, ensuring the dominance of its ideology.

 

Notably, ISAs are not only objects but also sites of class struggle. Unlike the (Repressive) State Apparatus, where the ruling class can exert direct control, ISAs face resistance from exploited classes, challenging hegemonic ideologies and seeking to assert their interests.

 

This discussion underscores the importance of understanding the role and significance of ISAs. They play a vital role in reproducing and contesting dominant ideologies, shaping social norms, and perpetuating or challenging power structures. Their function, rooted in ideology rather than coercion, is pivotal in maintaining class hegemony and perpetuating social order.

 

 

 

 

6

 

ON THE REPRODUCTION OF THE R ELATIONS OF PRODUCTION

Moving beyond the descriptive language of the base-superstructure metaphor, we can assert that it is primarily secured through the exercise of state power in the state apparatuses, namely the Repressive State Apparatus and the Ideological State Apparatuses.

 

This assertion can be summarized with three key features:

 

Dual Functionality: All state apparatuses operate through both repression and ideology. However, the (Repressive) State Apparatus predominantly relies on repression, while the Ideological State Apparatuses predominantly function through ideology.

 

Multiplicity and Autonomy: Unlike the centralized and unified organization of the (Repressive) State Apparatus, Ideological State Apparatuses are multiple, distinct, and relatively autonomous. They provide an objective field for expressing contradictions arising from class struggle.

 

Unity through Ruling Ideology: While the (Repressive) State Apparatus is unified under the leadership of the ruling class, the unity of the Ideological State Apparatuses is usually maintained, albeit in contradictory forms, through the ruling ideology.

 

Considering these features, the reproduction of the relations of production can be understood through a division of labor:

 

The Repressive State Apparatus primarily ensures the political conditions for the reproduction of exploitative relations of production through physical or administrative force. It not only perpetuates its own existence but also secures the conditions for the functioning of the Ideological State Apparatuses by enforcing political constraints, censorship, and other forms of repression.

 

In reality, it is the Ideological State Apparatuses (ISAs) that primarily ensure the reproduction of the relations of production, operating behind the protective shield provided by the Repressive State Apparatus. The ruling ideology, upheld by the ruling class holding state power, plays a central role in mediating a "harmony" between the Repressive State Apparatus and the various Ideological State Apparatuses.

 

Considering the diversity of ISAs and their shared role in reproducing relations of production, we can hypothesize the following:

 

In capitalist societies, numerous ISAs are at work, including the educational, religious, family, political, trade union, communications, and cultural apparatuses. However, in pre-capitalist feudal societies, the number of ISAs was smaller and their functions different. For instance, during the Middle Ages, the Church consolidated various functions, later devolved onto separate ISAs in capitalist societies. Alongside the Church, other ISAs such as the family, political, and proto-trade union apparatuses played significant roles.

 

Historically, the dominant ISA was the Church, which held religious, educational, and communicative functions. The French Revolution aimed not only to transfer state power but also to challenge the Church's dominant ideological role, leading to the establishment of new ISAs like the educational apparatus.

 

Despite the bourgeoisie's initial reliance on the political ISA, notably parliamentary democracy, for ideological hegemony, the educational ISA gradually assumed dominance. This shift was a result of violent political and ideological struggles aimed at replacing the old dominant ISAs with new ones better suited for the reproduction of capitalist relations of production.

 

Therefore, it can be argued that in mature capitalist societies, the educational ideological apparatus occupies the dominant position among ISAs, despite the common perception that the political ISA holds this role.

In recent history, the bourgeoisie has demonstrated its ability to adapt to various political Ideological State Apparatuses (ISAs) other than parliamentary democracy, such as empires, constitutional monarchy, and presidential democracy. For example, in France, different political regimes, including empires and constitutional monarchies, have coexisted with bourgeois interests. Similarly, in England, a compromise was reached between the bourgeoisie and the aristocracy, allowing them to share state power for an extended period. In Germany, the imperial Junkers facilitated the bourgeoisie's rise to power, even under the Nazi regime.

 

However, behind the scenes of political ISAs, the bourgeoisie has established the educational apparatus as its dominant ISA. This apparatus has replaced the Church in its functions and plays a crucial role in reproducing capitalist relations of production. Despite the common perception that the political ISA holds dominance, the educational apparatus is more influential.

 

The educational apparatus ensures the reproduction of capitalist relations of exploitation through various means:

 

Contributions to Reproduction: All ISAs contribute to reproducing capitalist relations, each in its unique way. The political apparatus subjects individuals to state ideology, while the communications apparatus instills nationalism and chauvinism through mass media. The religious apparatus reinforces moral values, and the family apparatus reinforces social norms.

 

Dominant Score: The ruling class's ideology dominates, integrating themes of humanism, nationalism, and economism into society's fabric.

 

Dominant Role of the School: Despite its silent nature, the school is the most influential ISA. It shapes children's ideologies from a young age, providing them with the knowledge and values necessary for their societal roles. Children receive education infused with the ruling ideology, preparing them for various class roles, from workers to capitalists, technicians to ideologists.

 

Class Role Indoctrination: Each segment of the population receives an ideology suited to its class role. Workers are instilled with a consciousness of exploitation, while agents of exploitation and repression are trained to maintain the status quo. Professional ideologists manipulate consciousnesses using moralistic and nationalistic rhetoric.

 

In essence, the educational apparatus serves as the primary vehicle for perpetuating capitalist relations of production, molding individuals into compliant members of the social hierarchy.

 

Certainly, many virtues and vices, such as modesty, cynicism, or confidence, are taught in various social institutions like the family, the Church, the military, literature, films, and even sports arenas. However, none of these institutions have the same widespread and obligatory audience as the educational system within capitalist societies. With children spending eight hours a day, five or six days a week in school, the educational apparatus becomes a powerful tool for the reproduction of capitalist relations of production.

 

Through the educational system, wrapped in the ideology of the ruling class, the relations between exploiters and exploited are largely perpetuated. This mechanism is obscured by the prevailing ideology of the school, which portrays it as a neutral and ideology-free environment where teachers, entrusted with children by their parents, guide them toward freedom and responsibility.

 

I must acknowledge the teachers who, despite difficult circumstances, strive to resist the dominant ideology and systems within which they operate. They are heroes in their own right. However, many teachers either fail to recognize or actively contribute to the perpetuation of the ideological representation of the school. Their dedication inadvertently sustains the belief that the school is a natural and beneficial institution, much like how the Church was perceived by previous generations.

 

Indeed, the school has replaced the Church as the dominant Ideological State Apparatus, functioning in tandem with the family. The current crisis affecting education systems worldwide, often paralleled by crises within family structures, holds significant political implications. The school, along with the family, plays a crucial role in reproducing the relations of production within capitalist societies, making it a prime target in the ongoing global class struggle.

7

 

V ON IDEOLOGY

The term "ideology" was originally coined by Cabanis, Destutt de Tracy, and their associates, who defined it as the study of ideas. However, when Marx adopted the term fifty years later, he imbued it with a fundamentally different meaning, even in his early writings. For Marx, ideology referred to the system of ideas and beliefs that shape the consciousness of individuals or social groups. His engagement in ideological and political struggles, evident in his early writings for the Rheinische Zeitung, compelled him to delve deeper into this concept.

 

Yet, we encounter an intriguing paradox here. Despite the natural inclination for Marx to develop a theory of ideology, his seminal works seem to skirt around the issue. Although The German Ideology, written after his 1844 Manuscripts, provides some insights into ideology, it is not distinctly Marxist. Similarly, while Capital contains references to various ideologies, particularly critiquing the ideas of the vulgar economists, it does not present a comprehensive theory of ideology itself, which relies heavily on a broader understanding of ideology.

 

With that said, I would like to propose a preliminary and schematic outline of such a theory. These propositions are not made lightly but require rigorous examination and analysis to be confirmed or refined.

 

Ideology h as no h istory

I want to begin by elucidating the fundamental rationale that underpins, or at least justifies, the endeavor to formulate a theory of ideology in general, rather than a theory of specific ideologies, which, regardless of their form (religious, ethical, legal, political), invariably reflect class positions.

 

It is evident that any theory of ideologies must encompass two essential dimensions, as previously suggested. Firstly, such a theory must be grounded in the history of social formations, including the modes of production operative within them, as well as the class struggles that unfold within these formations. In this regard, it becomes apparent that ideologies, defined within the dual framework mentioned earlier (regional and class), are historically contingent phenomena, their ultimate determination lying outside the realm of ideology alone, albeit intricately intertwined with it.

 

Conversely, while I propose the project of a theory of ideology in general, and assert its foundational role in theories of ideologies, this assertion implies a seemingly paradoxical proposition: ideology has no history.

 

This formulation, articulated explicitly in The German Ideology, marks a departure from a positivist and historicist perspective. In Marx's conception, ideology is depicted as an illusion, a mere dream devoid of substance. Its reality is extrinsic to it, akin to the theoretical status of dreams in pre-Freudian psychology.

 

Marx presents ideology as a constructed fabrication, a hollow semblance fashioned from the detritus of daily life, lacking intrinsic historical agency. Thus, the assertion that ideology has no history in The German Ideology is a negative assertion, signifying both the emptiness of ideology as a dream-like construct and its lack of inherent historical trajectory.

 

However, the thesis I advocate diverges markedly from the positivist stance of The German Ideology. I contend that while ideologies possess their own historical trajectory, albeit ultimately determined by the class struggle, ideology in general is devoid of historical specificity, but in a positive sense.

 

This positivist interpretation suggests that ideology exhibits a structural and functional constancy that renders it a non-historical reality—an omni-historical reality—permeating the fabric of history in an immutable form. This view aligns with Marx's characterization of history as the history of class struggles, emphasizing the continuity of ideology across different historical epochs marked by class societies.

 

To draw a theoretical parallel, I liken this proposition—ideology has no history—to Freud's assertion regarding the eternal nature of the unconscious. In Freudian terms, the unconscious is portrayed as an enduring, trans-historical entity, immutable in form throughout history. Similarly, ideology, conceived as eternal in this sense, persists unchanged across the sweep of history.

8

In light of these considerations, I posit that a theory of ideology in general, akin to Freud's theory of the unconscious, is theoretically warranted. For simplicity's sake, I employ the term "ideology" to denote ideology in general, which I have argued possesses an eternal, immutable character throughout the history of class societies. For now, I confine my analysis to class societies and their historical trajectory.

 

Ideology is a 'representation ' of the imaginary relationship of individuals to their real conditions of existence

 

 

To delve into my central thesis regarding the structure and operation of ideology, it's essential to present two theses—one negative and the other positive. The first thesis pertains to the object "represented" in the imaginary form of ideology, while the second thesis addresses the materiality of ideology.

 

THESIS I: Ideology represents the imaginary relationship of individuals to their real conditions of existence.

 

Commonly, we refer to religious ideology, ethical ideology, legal ideology, political ideology, and the like as "world outlooks." Even if we do not genuinely subscribe to these ideologies as truths (such as believing in God, Duty, Justice, etc.), we acknowledge them as largely imaginary—meaning they do not correspond to reality.

 

However, despite their lack of correspondence to reality, ideologies do allude to reality and can be interpreted to reveal the truth behind their imaginary representations (ideology = illusion/allusion).

 

Interpretations of ideologies vary, with some viewing them as constructs forged by priests or despots to manipulate and control individuals. Others, like Feuerbach and Marx, attribute the imaginary nature of ideologies to the alienating conditions of existence within society.

 

Regardless of the interpretation, all agree on one point: ideologies reflect the real conditions of existence of individuals, albeit in distorted and imaginary ways. However, I posit that ideologies primarily represent not the real conditions of existence themselves but rather the relationship of individuals to those conditions—a crucial distinction.

 

In Marxist terms, ideologies do not reflect the actual relations of production but rather the imaginary relationship of individuals to these relations. Thus, the question shifts from the cause of the imaginary distortion to why individuals perceive their relation to social relations in an imaginary manner and what characterizes this imaginariness.

 

This reframing of the question undermines simplistic explanations involving cliques or alienation, opening up a deeper exploration of the nature of ideology. However, I'll refrain from delving further into this topic for now.

THESIS II: Ideology possesses a material existence.

 

Previously, I hinted at this thesis by suggesting that the 'ideas' or 'representations' constituting ideology do not exist in an ideal or spiritual realm but rather have a material existence. While this assertion lacks formal proof, I ask the reader to entertain it favorably, given the principles of materialism. Demonstrating this thesis would require extensive argumentation.

 

The hypothetical proposition of the material existence of 'ideas' or other 'representations' proves useful in analyzing ideology more deeply. Specifically, it aids in understanding that ideologies always manifest within apparatuses and their practices, underscoring their material existence.

 

Although the material existence of ideology within apparatuses differs from that of tangible objects like stones or rifles, it remains rooted in physical matter. Moving forward, let's examine the individuals living within ideology—immersed in a specific representation of the world distorted by their imaginary relation to their conditions of existence, ultimately tied to relations of production and class.

 

Consider an individual who believes in concepts like God, Duty, or Justice. This belief stems from the ideas within the individual's consciousness, shaping their behavior and practical attitudes. For instance, a believer in God may attend church, pray, confess, and perform penance, while someone adhering to Duty may exhibit corresponding behaviors as dictated by their ideological beliefs.

 

Through this framework, we see that the ideological representation acknowledges that individuals, guided by their consciousness and beliefs, align their actions with their ideas. Failure to do so is deemed 'wicked,' suggesting a disconnect between professed beliefs and actual behavior. This discrepancy implies either inconsistency, cynicism, or perversion in the individual's adherence to ideology.

 

In every instance, the ideology of ideology acknowledges, despite its distorted nature, that the 'ideas' of a human subject manifest in their actions or should manifest in their actions. If this alignment is lacking, the ideology assigns the individual other ideas corresponding to their performed actions, even if those actions are perverse. This ideology speaks of actions, whereas I will refer to actions embedded within practices. These practices are governed by rituals within the material existence of an ideological apparatus, whether it's a small religious gathering, a funeral, a sports match, a school day, or a political party meeting.

 

Pascal's provocative statement—"Kneel down, move your lips in prayer, and you will believe"—inverts the conventional order of things, challenging individuals to engage in actions that may lead to belief. This provocative inversion, akin to Christ's disruptive message, brings forth not peace but strife and scandal. Pascal's bold approach underscores the tangible reality behind beliefs.

 

Leaving Pascal to his theological debates, I'll adopt a more directly Marxist vocabulary for our exploration of these concepts. Thus, when considering a single individual, the material existence of their beliefs lies in their actions within practices governed by rituals dictated by the material ideological apparatus. These actions are influenced by the ideas derived from that apparatus. Although these actions may vary in their materiality—from physical gestures to verbal discourse—their essence lies in their manifestation within material practices.

 

This rearrangement of concepts results in the disappearance of the term 'ideas' as purely ideal or spiritual entities. Instead, emphasis shifts to the subject, consciousness, belief, and actions. The critical term here is the subject. From this understanding, two interconnected theses emerge:

 

There is no practice without ideology.

There is no ideology without the subject, and ideology serves the subjects.

With these foundational principles in mind, I can now present my central thesis.

 

 

9

Ideology interpellates individuals as subjects

This thesis is a matter of explicitly stating my previous proposition: there is no ideology except by the subject and for subjects. This means that ideology only exists for concrete subjects, and its purpose is enabled by the subject, specifically by the category of the subject and its functioning.

 

The category of the subject, though it may appear under various names throughout history, such as the soul in Plato or God, is the fundamental category of all ideology. It constitutes all ideology, regardless of its regional or class-based determinations or historical context, since ideology is timeless.

 

I argue that the category of the subject is constitutive of all ideology because ideology functions to constitute concrete individuals as subjects. In this dual constitution lies the essence of all ideology, which manifests as the functioning of ideology in the material forms of its existence.

 

To understand this further, it's crucial to realize that both the writer and the reader are themselves subjects and therefore ideological subjects. We live naturally in ideology, as it forms the basis of our consciousness and beliefs.

 

As St. Paul eloquently stated, it is in the 'Logos', or ideology, that we 'live, move, and have our being'. Thus, the category of the subject is an inherent 'obviousness' for you and me, as we naturally recognize ourselves as subjects. This recognition is an ideological effect, as ideology imposes obviousnesses upon us, leading to our natural acceptance and affirmation of them.

 

An example of this ideological recognition is when we identify ourselves or others in everyday interactions, such as answering 'It's me' when asked who is at the door. These rituals of recognition reaffirm our individuality and subjectivity.

 

However, recognizing ourselves as subjects and engaging in these rituals of recognition only provides us with consciousness of our ideological practices. It does not give us scientific knowledge of the mechanism behind this recognition. It is this knowledge that we must strive to attain, breaking free from ideology to begin a scientific discourse on ideology.

To illustrate why the category of the 'subject' is constitutive of ideology, which only exists by constituting concrete subjects as subjects, I will utilize a specific mode of exposition: one that is concrete enough to be recognized yet abstract enough to be thought and understood as knowledge.

 

Firstly, I propose that all ideology hails or interpellates concrete individuals as concrete subjects through the functioning of the category of the subject. This suggests a distinction between concrete individuals and concrete subjects, although at this level, concrete subjects only exist as supported by concrete individuals.

 

Ideology 'acts' or 'functions' in a manner that 'recruits' subjects from individuals or transforms individuals into subjects through a process of interpellation or hailing. This process can be imagined akin to everyday police hailing: 'Hey, you there!'

 

In this scenario, when an individual is hailed, they turn around, thus becoming a subject by recognizing that the hail was addressed to them. This recognition occurs seamlessly, indicating the immediate and inherent connection between ideology and the individual's subjectivity.

What seems to take place outside ideology, such as in the street, actually occurs within ideology. The practical workings of ideology often lead individuals to believe they are outside ideology, but in reality, they are entrenched within it. Ideology never identifies itself as such; it's only through scientific knowledge that one can recognize their immersion in ideology.

 

Thus, ideology continually interpellates individuals as subjects. As ideology is eternal, I must abandon the temporal framework and assert that ideology has always-already interpellated individuals as subjects. Consequently, individuals are always-already subjects.

10

 

This may seem paradoxical, but it's the undeniable reality. Even before birth, individuals are appointed as subjects within familial ideological configurations. For example, an unborn child is already expected to bear its father's name, signifying its identity and irreplaceability before birth.

 

This familial ideological structure pre-appoints the child as a subject, shaping its future role as a sexual subject based on societal norms and expectations. This ideological constraint is reflected in Freud's exploration of pre-genital and genital stages of sexuality, which are deeply ingrained in the unconscious.

 

Moving forward, I will explore how the 'actors' in this scene of interpellation and their roles are reflected in the structure of all ideology.

 

An example: the Christian religious ideology

 

The formal structure of all ideology remains constant, so I will focus on a single example - religious ideology, which can be extended to other forms such as ethical, legal, political, and aesthetic ideologies.

 

Consider Christian religious ideology. In a fictional discourse, it might express:

"I address you, Peter, a human individual, to proclaim that God exists and you are accountable to Him. God speaks through my voice, affirming your identity as Peter, created by God for eternity but born in the year of Our Lord 1920. Your place in the world and your actions determine your salvation, granting you membership in the Glorious Body of Christ."

 

This discourse, though familiar, is surprising in its implications. Religious ideology aims to transform individuals into subjects by interpellating them - calling them by their names and designating roles and destinies for them based on their obedience to divine commands.

 

However, what's remarkable is that this process depends on the existence of a Unique, Absolute Other Subject: God. This capital "Subject" interpellates individuals as subjects in His name, as evident in religious scriptures where God addresses Moses, who acknowledges his subjectivity and obeys God's commandments.

 

God defines Himself as the Subject par excellence, who interpellates individuals like Moses, making them subjects subjected to Him. In theological reflection, humans are seen as mirrors or reflections of God, made in His image. God needs subjects, just as subjects need God, forming a reciprocal relationship where even in their debauchery, subjects fulfill God's need for them.

 

God duplicates Himself by sending His Son to Earth, as a subject forsaken by Him but also as the Subject, both man and God, to pave the way for final Redemption - the Resurrection of Christ. This duplication underscores the necessity for the Subject to become a subject, and vice versa, to tangibly demonstrate to individuals that they are subjects subjected to the Subject, with the ultimate goal of re-entering the Lord's Bosom on Judgment Day.

 

Deciphering this necessity, we find that all ideology operates within a mirror-structure, interpellating individuals as subjects in the name of a Unique and Absolute Subject. This mirror duplication is central to ideology, ensuring its functioning. The Absolute Subject occupies the unique Center and interpellates individuals around it, subjecting them to the Subject while providing them the guarantee that they are recognized and saved.

 

In summary, the mirror-structure of ideology ensures the interpellation of individuals as subjects, their subjection to the Subject, mutual recognition, and absolute guarantee. Caught in this system, subjects work by themselves, obedient to various authorities dictated by ideology. The ambiguity of the term "subject" reflects the effect of this system: individuals are interpellated as free subjects to freely accept their subjection, thus working by themselves to reproduce the relations of production and maintain the socio-technical division of labor.

 

While the preceding theses shed light on certain aspects of the superstructure's functioning and its intervention in the base, they inevitably leave several important issues unresolved, which merit acknowledgment:

 

The problem of the total process of reproducing the relations of production.

The role of Ideological State Apparatuses (ISAs) in this process is crucial, yet viewing their contribution alone remains abstract. The actual realization of reproduction occurs within the processes of production and circulation, where mechanisms train workers, assign posts, etc. However, in a class society, production relations entail exploitation and antagonistic class relations. Therefore, reproduction cannot be a mere technical operation; it's a class undertaking realized through class struggle.

 

The class nature of ideologies in a social formation.

While the mechanism of ideology can be abstractly articulated, it must be contextualized within real ideological formations. Ideologies manifest in institutions, rituals, and practices, contributing to the ruling class's reproduction of power. However, ideologies are not realized in a vacuum; they stem from class struggle and the conditions, experiences, and practices of antagonistic classes.

 

Understanding the class struggle within ISAs is vital, but it's just one aspect of a broader struggle. ISAs represent where ruling ideologies are realized and challenged, but ideologies originate from the social classes engaged in the struggle. Therefore, ideologies are not born within ISAs but emerge from the conditions and experiences of conflicting classes. Thus, only from the perspective of classes and their struggle can the origins and dynamics of ideologies in a social formation be fully comprehended.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

No comments:

Post a Comment

Eric Sean Nelson, "Hermeneutics: Schleiermacher and Dilthey" (Summary)

Friedrich Schleiermacher and Wilhelm Dilthey are often considered representatives of nineteenth-century hermeneutics and hermeneutical philo...