Radical intellectuals often express frustration at what they
perceive as an excessive focus on conceptualization, finding dialectical
language unnecessarily complex and obscure. A significant challenge for
rational minds engaging with dialectics lies in the fluidity of Marx's
concepts, which can resemble bats, showing both birdlike and mouselike
attributes depending on the context (Pareto, cited on p. 4). Among the clearest
elucidations of Marx's dialectical approach is the extensive body of work by
Bertell Ollman, a selection of which is compiled here.
Ollman contends that Marx primarily employed dialectical
presentation in his unpublished notebooks rather than in works intended for
publication. This preference stems from Marx's belief that conceptualization
shapes perception. Dialectics, according to Ollman, is apt for a world
characterized by mutually dependent dynamic processes, making it particularly
relevant to capitalism—a vast, intricate, integrated, and holistic system whose
structure often remains obscured, contributing to fragmentation in individual
and social existence.
Analyzing Marx's method into six categories—ontology,
epistemology, inquiry, intellectual reconstruction, exposition, and
praxis—reveals his deep commitment to viewing the world as a systemic whole.
Epistemologically, Marx dissects this whole into structured, interdependent,
relational units. His inquiry delves into the links constituting this whole,
culminating in conceptual reconstruction. Exposition, driven by heuristic and
political motives, and praxis, involving conscious action, also play
significant roles. Ollman emphasizes Marx's adoption of a philosophy of
internal relations from Hegel, Leibniz, and Spinoza, which doubles into
ontology and epistemology.
Contrary to banal realism, Marx, according to Ollman, sees
reality's essence lying in the fundamental relations between entities rather
than merely their existence apart from the investigator's experiences. The
substantial existence of nature, Marx argues, is only comprehensible as a
whole, with parts serving as relational constructs abstracted from reality,
their interdependence constituting the whole. This perspective extends common
sense, positing that a thing incorporates the conditions of its existence and
that the whole is inherent in each of its parts. Marx regards the relations
among things as "internal," including their interactive context.
Ollman terms such entities, along with their necessary conditions and outcomes,
"relations." Internal relations, he argues, are systematically
necessary, while external relations entail contingency. Since the theoretical
object is in constant flux, a thing encompasses its evolutionary process, along
with its systemic relations.
In essence, Ollman's interpretation underscores Marx's
dialectical approach as a powerful cognitive tool, particularly suited to
understanding the complexities of capitalism. Marx's methodological framework
encompasses ontology, epistemology, inquiry, intellectual reconstruction,
exposition, and praxis, with a focus on the philosophy of internal relations.
This perspective challenges conventional realism by emphasizing the
interdependence and systemic nature of entities, positing that understanding
reality necessitates grasping its relational dynamics. Ollman's elucidation
enriches our understanding of Marx's dialectical methodology and its
implications for comprehending social and economic systems.
Marx's epistemology is rooted in an ontological commitment
to society as a system, leading to a rationalist imperative for systemic
coherence as a truth criterion. Abstraction, among Ollman's four
epistemological aspects, plays a central role. In everyday consciousness,
perception follows intuitive, socialized abstraction, with concepts situating
abstractions within existing knowledge's social flux. The transition from
everyday to systematic consciousness, driven by ontological commitment and
epistemological imperative, shifts focus from independent factors to
understanding specific relational meanings of concepts. Abstraction delineates
boundaries, analyzing wholes into manageable cognitive units for mental
reconstruction, facilitating inquiry, organization, and exposition, focusing on
change and interaction in a internally related systemic reality. Theory employs
abstraction to carve up reality for its purposes.
Ollman breaks down abstraction into perspective, level of
generality, and extension. Perspectives may involve categories such as
individual, class, or group interests. Levels of generality range from unique individuals
to broader entities like modern capitalism or the material world, each
highlighting specific attributes. Abstractions at higher levels constrain
possibilities at lower levels, while actions at lower levels may ground those
at higher levels. Extension, spatial and temporal, influences a concept's
meaning. Ollman emphasizes that claims of identity and identity-in-difference,
central to dialectical contradiction, require an abstraction broad enough to
encompass both sameness and difference. For instance, rent, profit, and
interest are distinct but identical as forms of surplus value in a wider
abstraction. Ollman suggests that Marx's epistemology combines empiricism and
rationalism, employing realist notions of conditions of existence deduced from past
and present societal observations. Marx avoids teleology and historical
determinism by viewing future alternatives as present potentials and the
present as a precondition for the future.
Ollman's work presents a valuable contribution, particularly
in its accessible treatment of a complex and contentious body of thought. His
pragmatic approach to dialectics is likely to persuade intellectually curious
individuals of the necessity for a nuanced understanding of knowledge
development. However, while Ollman's treatment of earlier developments in
dialectics is robust, his handling of more recent developments is less
satisfactory.
Ollman criticizes contemporary "new" or systematic
dialectics for purported gaps that may not actually exist. His delineation of
dialectic in terms of "moment" and "form," appearance and
essence, resembles aspects of the very systematic dialectics he critiques.
Nonetheless, Ollman's insights into Marx's dialectic—uncovering relationships,
acknowledging its unfinished nature, revisions, and multiplicity of
perspectives—have significantly influenced contemporary dialectical thought.
Contemporary dialectics has built upon Ollman's groundwork, recognizing the
centrality of developmental and organic interconnections, utilizing capitalist contradictions
to glimpse post-revolutionary futures, critiquing capitalism through its
defenders, addressing both capitalist reality and its conceptualization, and
emphasizing synthesis in dialectical explanation.
While Ollman's contribution is immense, his characterization
of contemporary dialectics as neglecting dynamic development in favor of
organic structure seems erroneous. Instead, contemporary dialectics agrees with
Ollman's insight that past development is best understood from the present
vantage point, a notion Ollman aptly phrases as "studying history
backward." Systematic dialectics, though narrower in focus compared to
Ollman's comprehensive account, is integral to understanding capitalism's
value-form methodology, critically building upon Ollman's foundations.
Similarly, Ollman's discussion of critical realism in
Chapter 10 appears superficial and possibly misinformed. It prompts broader
reflections on the relationship between being and consciousness often
overlooked by realists. Rather than privileging either epistemology or
ontology, as Ollman suggests, a dialectical approach seeks to problematize any
simplistic dichotomy between them. Ollman argues for the interdependence of
perception and conception, bridging this divide with the term "epistemontology,"
capturing the paradoxical unity-in-difference between them.
For Ollman, reality as perceived is conceptualized,
reflecting an ontological commitment to the objects of those concepts, which,
in turn, shape perceptual possibilities. However, Bhaskar's naturalism blurs
the distinction between ontological commitment to a mind-independent world and
the social reality shaped by everyday consciousness. Reflexivity ensures that
agents' conceptions drive actions, potentially reproducing and transforming
social reality. Social reality, while independent of the scientific observer's
mind directly, remains entwined with the phenomenological mind, which is
inherently social and constitutive of society.
Dialectics, with its flexibility in scope and focus, allows
concepts to shift meaning as they adjust their denotation over relations,
influenced by both theoretical concerns and the nature of relations and
systems. Ollman grapples with the tensions of "epistemontology,"
conceiving dialectic as both a predicate of the ontological totality,
capitalism, and the epistemology to grasp it. While Ollman's emphasis on the
philosophy of internal relations positing all reality as a single totality may
seem implausible, Bhaskar's idea of multiple totalities with internal relations
within each is preferred. Despite some repetition, Ollman's work offers
pragmatic insights into dialectical investigation, serving as a potential
handbook on Marxist dialectical method. However, the later chapters lack the
depth of critique promised, with the final chapter on Japan's capitalist class
being largely descriptive. While dialectics may be unproven for many social
scientists, Ollman's focus on its application to political science makes this
collection valuable for radical social scientists.
No comments:
Post a Comment