Aesthetic attitude
theories emphasize the importance of the aesthetic attitude in understanding
art and its relationship with other values. Some argue that the nature of art
is explained by the aesthetic attitude, but this view is generally accepted as insufficient
for setting the boundaries of art. Most aesthetic attitude theories offer
subtler and more complex accounts of the interaction among the aesthetic
attitude, art, and beauty.
The origins of aesthetic attitude theory can be traced back to the eighteenth-century
notion of disinterest, which was discussed by a group of British thinkers
writing about beauty and taste. Lord Shaftesbury, Immanuel Kant, and Arthur
Schopenhauer were among the early to discuss the notion in depth. These
philosophers wrote about aesthetics and art, often referred to as theories of
taste, because they each essentially involve the notion of a special kind of
faculty, the faculty of taste, that we use to determine an object's aesthetic
value.
The relationship between the aesthetic attitude and eighteenth-century British
theories of taste is a subject of debate. Some philosophers, like Jerome
Stolnitz, argue that there is a deep continuity between these two groups of
theories, while others, like George Dickie, argue that there is an important
divide between the two groups of theories. However, it is hard to deny any
connection, as these British philosophers influenced Kant and inspired everyone
who has written about the aesthetic attitude since.
Shaftesbury, Francis Hutcheson, and David Hume were prominent British
philosophers who wrote about aesthetics and art. Their theories are often
referred to as theories of taste because they each essentially involve the
notion of a special kind of faculty, the faculty of taste, that we use to
determine an object's aesthetic value. Later British theorists, such as Edmund
Burke, argued against such a faculty, worrying that it failed to explain
anything.
Shaftesbury argues that aesthetic experience is disinterested, but has a
Platonic picture on which beauty is essentially the same as goodness and truth.
Aesthetic appreciation is not devoid of any connection whatsoever to other
values (ethical and epistemological), despite lacking connection to our
personal ends and interests. For him, appreciating something aesthetically
involves the same essential feeling as appreciating something morally.
Hutcheson and Hume disagree with Shaftesbury's unified view, rejecting the
equivalence of beauty, goodness, and truth and seeing more of a gap between aesthetic
value and other values. They all share the central idea of disinterested
pleasure as independent from personal interest, which forms the starting point
for aesthetic attitude theories.
Kant's aesthetic attitude theory focuses on our judgments of taste, also known
as judgments of taste or judgments of the beautiful. These judgments involve
four important aspects: disinterestedness, universality, purposiveness without
purpose, and necessity. Disinterest is the quality of our judgments of taste, which
are subjective and come from our feelings rather than objective facts.
Kant argues that there are three kinds of satisfaction: agreeable, beautiful,
and good. The agreeable gratifies some desire, while the beautiful is
disinterested pleasure. The agreeable pleasure serves our purpose, and our
finding it depends on our psychology. We cannot change what we desire simply by
willing to.
The good is esteemed and approved, with objective value set on it. We find
being generous good when we set objective value on generosity or generous
actions. Pleasure in the good is also interested, as reason determines what we
find good. This is still a personal interest because each person has an
interest in bringing about the good.
The beautiful is disinterested pleasure, and the art collector who enjoys her
artwork for its monetary value enjoys that work in an interested way, and thus
has not taken the aesthetic attitude toward it. Consequently, any positive
judgment she produces will not be a judgment of taste. Kant takes this idea
further, arguing that anyone who really approaches something with a
contemplative, disinterested attitude and finds it beautiful (that is, takes
the aesthetic attitude toward it) will not even be interested in whether the
object in fact exists. To want the object to exist is to have an interest
wrapped up in it, or in other words, to have something be at stake in its
existence.
There are three other conditions of judgments of taste: they must be universal,
which means they feel as though they apply to everyone. Calling something
beautiful means feeling like everyone should recognize it as beautiful (even if
we realize that it is not a fact about the object that it is beautiful). The
objects of these judgments also exhibit what Kant calls purposiveness without
purpose, or alternatively, finality without an end. This may sound complex but
just means that while there may be no actual purpose of the object (or at least
not one of which we are aware), we are struck by how it seems to be made for a purpose.
Lastly, these judgments are necessary in the sense that it feels like we judge
according to some unspoken universal rule, from which our judgment necessarily
follows. Disinterest, a notion first brought to the fore by the
eighteenth-century British philosophers, continues to be a central notion in
Kant's aesthetics. However, Kant does not seem to have a true aesthetic
attitude theory in the sense defined above. It is a matter of interpretation,
but it looks as though he does not think that any object we approach with this
frame of mind thereby becomes an aesthetic object. Many argue that it is not
until Schopenhauer, for whom disinterest is even more important, that we see an
actual aesthetic attitude theory.
Schopenhauer's aesthetic attitude theory, which he introduced in his book
"The World as Will and Representation," is a philosophical approach
that focuses on the world as a representation rather than a Will.
Schopenhauer's philosophy is characterized by a focus on the Will, which is a
unceasing desire that forms the basis of human suffering. He believes that
experiencing the world as Will leads to boredom and deeper suffering.
Schopenhauer's aesthetic attitude theory suggests that we should not look at
things in the ordinary way, which involves both perceptual meaning and
non-perceptual one. Instead, we should pay attention to the surface features of
an object and its relationships to other things. This relational viewing is
absent in the aesthetic attitude, where we only pay attention to things themselves.
Schopenhauer also emphasizes that we should not have abstract thought or
reasoning, but instead focus on the perception alone. This approach fills our
mind with calm contemplation, allowing us to stop thinking about the will and
no longer sense a difference between ourselves and the object perceived. This
means that we can see through the object itself to its Idea, which are eternal
and unchangeable.
Aesthetic contemplation allows us to know the Ideas, which are eternal and
unchangeable. Anything can become the object of the aesthetic attitude, as
everything represents Ideas and manifests the will in some way. This means that
Schopenhauer's aesthetic attitude theory has profound practical import, as it
can release us from the cycle of constant suffering and help us deal with
difficult situations.
However, it is important to note that taking the aesthetic attitude is not easy
and comes naturally to everyone. While some artistic geniuses can actively
adopt the aesthetic attitude, others may remain in that state for longer than
the typical fleeting moment. Schopenhauer answers that the aesthetic attitude
is a mix of these, with some people being more adept at engaging it actively
while others are a transient and happenstance state.
In Schopenhauer's view, attention and perception take center stage, and
aesthetic contemplation involves intense focus where the perception completely
fills the mind. The aesthetic attitude plays a crucial role in the larger
theory, helping us know Ideas and by doing so, releases us from endless
suffering.
While many aspects of Schopenhauer's view have resonated with subsequent
philosophers of aesthetics, to fully adopt his view, one must adopt much of the
rest of his philosophy, which includes his theory of Ideas, representation, and
the Will. Later aesthetic attitude theorists often preserve some key aspects of
the view, but they are generally unwilling to do so.
Sunday, 12 May 2024
Aesthetic Attitude (History)
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Raymond Williams, "Modern Tragedy" (Book Note)
Raymond Williams’s Modern Tragedy offers a nuanced re-evaluation of the concept of tragedy by moving beyond classical definitions and situa...
-
The feminist economics project has made significant strides. This progress is particularly notable as feminist economics has transitioned ...
-
Armstrong's theory of the novel is distinct from Watt's, as she places greater emphasis on the history of female subjectivity and ...
-
The Process of Recording and Consumption • The process of recording and consumption is akin to the production of production, with the produ...
No comments:
Post a Comment