Pragmatism, the most significant
intellectual movement in the United States, was influenced by the writings of
Charles Sanders Peirce, Josiah Royce, William James, George Santayana, John
Dewey, and George Herbert Mead in the first half of the twentieth century, and
Wilfrid Sellars, W. V. O. Quine, Hilary Putnam, Nelson Goodman, and Richard
Rorty in the second half. The various forms of pragmatism differ mainly in
terms of their dependence on experience or language, and the paradigmatic
status accorded to natural science.
American philosophers who dealt with religion from the 1870s to the 1930s
brought both naturalism and pragmatism to bear on topics such as religious
experience, the meaning and reference of "God," the nature of
religious truth, and the community of interpreters. Charles Sanders Peirce, the
founder of pragmatism, worked as a logician, experimental scientist, and
mathematician, and his theories were governed by a conception of evolutionary
change. He believed that beliefs were treated as habits of action, and truth
was defined as inquiry.
Peirce was an early anti-foundalist, abandoning the Cartesian quest for
incorrigible grounds for knowledge claims. His metaphysical investigations
defended the threefold claim of synechism, tychism, and agapeism, and developed
a complex and intricate system out of three simple categories of possibility,
actuality, and necessity or law.
In his 1908 essay, "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God,"
philosopher John Peirce introduced the Humble Argument, which concluded that
God is real and rational belief in God is universally accessible. The argument
highlighted musement and abduction as common stages of scientific or religious
inquiry. Musement was a process of thought reasonably tending to produce a definitive
belief, while abduction was a generative process neither deduced from
evidential premises nor inductively generalized from them.
Peirce believed religion was a universal sentiment, more a way of living than a
way of believing. His theism was left somewhat vague, functioning as a
regulative hope of the possibility of inquiry. Commentators are divided on
whether Peirce's theism should be interpreted according to process philosophy
in a panentheistic way (Donna Orange) or in a more traditional Thomistic
direction (Michael Raposa).
William James' chief contributions to philosophy of religion are often
associated only with his arguments in The Will to Believe (1897) and his
conclusions in The Varieties of Religious Experience (1902). He argued that an individual
has a right to believe a hypothesis that cannot be proved by direct evidence,
but overinflationated the distinction between intellectual and passional
interests and problematically defined the religious hypothesis to mean "
perfection is eternal."
James became too good a historicist over the course of his career to remain
content with stale dualisms between nature and supernature, the temporal and
the eternal, the physical and the mental. Radical empiricism complemented his
pragmatism, providing a notion of "experience" that could bear the
weight of a naturalized theory of religious experience while avoiding the
charge of subjectivism invited by The Varieties.
Peirce's Humble Argument and James' radical empiricism were significant
contributions to the field of philosophy of religion. While they both
contributed to the understanding of religious experience, their differing
approaches and perspectives have shaped our understanding of the world around
us.
James formulated his pluralistic pantheism, rejecting the monistic view that
the divine exists authentically only when the world is experienced all at once
in its absolute totality. He envisioned a single universe of nature in which
the whole is neither absolutely one nor absolutely many, and both human and
non-human powers cooperate together. The whole exhibits "concatenated
unity" or a multiplicity of irreducibly particular events in the midst of
intricate patterns of relatedness.
James was willing to believe that there may ultimately never be an all-form at
all, that the substance of reality may never get totally collected, and that
some of it may remain outside of the largest combination of it ever made. The
pluralistic world is more like a federal republic than like an empire or a
kingdom. While monism and pluralism can stimulate stressful moods, James
believed that the world's salvation depend upon the energizing of its several
parts, among which we are.
John Dewey aimed to divorce the meaning of the adjective "religious"
from the traditional sense of the noun "religion." He defined the
religious as any activity pursued in behalf of an ideal end against obstacles
and in spite of threats of personal loss because of conviction of its general
and enduring value. Life was lived with a religious quality whenever and
wherever anyone experienced a sense of human nature as a cooperating part of a
larger whole.
Dewey proposed three proposals for how the self is integrated as a whole:
first, the religious aspect of experience pointed to some complex of conditions
that operated to effect a significant adjustment in life, a transformative and
integrative reorientation. Second, imagination played a key role in unifying
the self in harmony with its surroundings. Both the ideal of the whole self and
the American pragmatism ideal of the totality of the world were held as
imaginative projections, but the work of self-integration was dependent on an
inflow from sources beyond conscious deliberation and purpose.
Dewey's pragmatic naturalism captured the evolutionary, processive-relational
sense of "uniting" as an ongoing activity. He struggled to slough off
the vestiges of idealism by affiliating the "continuity" of the many
with each other as many, but not their literal oneness.
Dewey's philosophy of religion, criticized for offering only a form of secular
humanism and excessive optimism, had more resonance and breadth than A Common
Faith alone reveals. He believed that consummatory experiences of quality or
value were the very aim of human praxis. In aesthetic experience, the
continuities of form and matter appeared directly and with consummatory power
that was a good in itself. Works of art created a sense of communion which
could generate or shade off into religious quality. The sense of belonging to a
whole which accompanied intense aesthetic perception also explained the
religious feeling.
Nature in turn was understood as both thwarting and supporting human efforts.
Humankind was continuous with and dependent upon an environing world which
should evoke heartfelt piety as the source of ideals, possibilities, and
aspirations. This made natural piety a genuine and valuable part of human life
in the world, needing more careful cultivation and expression to play a
positive role in the development of society and culture.
Dewey repeatedly appealed to "a sense of the whole," "the sense
of an enveloping whole," that is experienced as a natural response of the
human organism to its environment. The religious, reconstructed
naturalistically, represented an intensification and broadening of the
aesthetic quality of experience, having to do with what Dewey called
"consummatory moments" involving fulfillments and immediately enjoyed
meanings. Wholeness was the quality that linked aesthetic experiences, ordinary
secular experiences, and religious experiences.
Dewey's final verdict was that the conditions and forces in nature and culture
that promote human well-being were plural. In contrast to H. N. Wieman's
thesis, he found no inherent unity to the forces and factors which made for
good, and the organizing and integrating of these forces or factors was the
work of human imagination and action.
Pragmatism is a philosophical approach that emphasizes antifoundationalism,
pluralism, and secular forms of transcendence without otherworldliness. It is
influenced by various American philosophers of religion, such as Jeffrey
Stout's modest pragmatism, H.S. Levinson's festive Jewish American pragmatic
naturalism, Cornel West's prophetic pragmatism, William Dean's naturalistic
historicism, and Sheila Davaney's pragmatic historicism. These authors
emphasize that religious beliefs are tools for dealing with reality, focusing
on historically contingent forms of consensus and social practice within
religious communities. They view commitment to democratic communal activism as
a consequence of pragmatism in religious American life and thought.
A significant shift in contemporary pragmatism occurred with the work of
Willard V. O. Quine, Donald Davidson, and Richard Rorty. These "linguistic
pragmatists" combined a naturalistic, Darwinian view of human life with an
antifoundationalist, holist account of meaning and truth. A fruitful area of
research for philosophy of religion's habitual interest in the concept of
"truth" is now open, with some pragmatist philosophers of religion
ready to jettison the pragmatist theory of truth in favor of the holist
account.
Pragmatism also challenges the use of distinctions such as
cognitive-noncognitive, scheme-content, objective-subjective, intellectual-emotionive,
and the reinstatement of the vague in human understanding. Exploring the
transitions, felt qualities, and indeterminacies of experience is essential for
a pragmatist reconstruction of the causes, consequences, and reference range of
religious phenomena.
Tuesday, 11 June 2024
American Pragmatism
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Raymond Williams, "Modern Tragedy" (Book Note)
Raymond Williams’s Modern Tragedy offers a nuanced re-evaluation of the concept of tragedy by moving beyond classical definitions and situa...
-
The feminist economics project has made significant strides. This progress is particularly notable as feminist economics has transitioned ...
-
Armstrong's theory of the novel is distinct from Watt's, as she places greater emphasis on the history of female subjectivity and ...
-
The Process of Recording and Consumption • The process of recording and consumption is akin to the production of production, with the produ...
No comments:
Post a Comment