Aquinas emphasized the
importance of scientific knowledge (scientia) and the existence of
non-scientific forms of knowledge, such as sense knowledge and knowledge of
self-evident propositions. He compared faith and scientia as subjectively
certain, with faith being grounded in compelling reasons and understanding why
they compel belief. In contrast, scientia is grounded in rational belief that
someone else has scientia or intellectual vision, such as divine faith.
For Aquinas, scientia is used analogously to science, which involves drawing
conclusions from things we already know. He contrasts science as an act of
inquiry with contemplation, which is a speculative activity with truth as its
immediate object. Aquinas believes that scientific inquiry aims to discover a
truth not already known, while contemplation aims to enjoy a truth already
known.
Science can be seen as an act of inquiry and a strong argument for the truth of
a proposition, known as a scientific demonstration. If a person possesses a
scientific demonstration of a proposition, they understand an argument that is
logically valid and knows with certainty that the premises are true.
Aquinas recognizes the Aristotelian sense of scientia as an intellectual habit
or disposition that involves the possession of scientific demonstrations and
knowledge about a subject matter. This habit is more than the fruit of inquiry
and the possession of arguments; it involves knowing the basic facts,
principles, causes, and logical connections between these facts. A person with
a science of a subject has systematic and controlled knowledge, allowing them
to speak about it with ease, coherence, clarity, and profundity.
Aquinas notes that the first principles of a science are sometimes naturally
known by the scientist, but sacred theology does not fit this characterization
of science. The first principles of sacred theology are articles of faith, not
known by the natural light of reason but by the grace of God. However,
contemporary philosophers of science would not find sacred theology's inability
to fit neatly into a well-defined univocal conception of science a problem for
its scientific status.
Sacred theology draws on principles known by those with a higher science, in
this case, the science possessed by God and the blessed. Despite not being
known by the natural light of reason, sacred theology is still a science, as
those who possess such a science can draw logical conclusions from the articles
of faith, argue that one article of faith is logically consistent with other
articles of faith, and answer objections to the articles of faith.
Aquinas' understanding of science is more restrictive than contemporary
notions, as he believes that we know something scientifically only if our knowledge
of it is certain. This is based on demonstrative knowledge, which begins from
premises we know with certainty by way of reflection upon sense experience.
However, modern notions of science often make claims of science fallible and
uncertain.
In his philosophy of science, Aquinas believes that the most capacious
scientific account of a physical object or event involves mentioning its four
causes: efficient, material, formal, and final causes. He believes that
material objects, whether natural or artificial, have four causes: material
cause (what O is made of), formal cause (what O is), final cause (what the end,
goal, purpose, or function of O is), and efficient cause (what brings or
conserves O in(to) being).
The Efficient Cause is a being that acts to bring or conserve a feature F in x.
Aquinas thinks that there are different kinds of efficient causes, such as God
being the primary efficient cause of any created being and creatures being
secondary efficient causes. God is the primary efficient cause as creator ex
nihilo, while creatures are secondary efficient causes in the sense that they
work on pre-existing matter such that matter that is merely potentially F
actually becomes F.
In conclusion, Aquinas' philosophy of science is more restrictive than
contemporary notions, but it is still a valuable perspective on the nature of
knowledge and the role of the four causes in understanding and addressing the
world.
Aquinas's concept of "material cause" is crucial for understanding
change and the subject of change. He believes that the material cause for a
substantial change is prima materia (prime or first matter), which is the
intrinsic cause of a substance that can undergo substantial change. Aquinas
believes that substances are unified objects of the highest order, and if
substantial changes had actual substances functioning as the ultimate subjects,
then it would be reasonable to question the substantial existence of those
substances.
Prime matter is the ultimate material cause of a substance that can undergo
substantial change, and it never exists without being configured by some form.
Matter always exists under dimensions, and this prime matter is configured by
the accidental form of quantity, specifically the accidental quantity of
existing in three dimensions. It is never the case that some prime matter
exists without being configured by some substantial form.
The theoretical significance of the view that material substances are composed
of prime matter as a part is that prime matter is the material causal
explanation of the fact that a material substance's generation and potential
corruption are changes that are real, substantial, natural, and intelligible.
For example, a quantity of prime matter might be configured by the substantial
form of an insect, living cells, chemical compounds, or incorporated into the
body of a frog.
Aquinas's formal cause can be understood in three ways: the nature or
definition of a thing, intrinsic to or inheres in a substance, and the pattern
or definition of a thing insofar as it exists in the mind of the maker. He
believes that all substances have final causes, but not all substances have
functions.
For Aquinas, the formal cause of a substance is the end, goal, purpose, or
function of the object. For example, a knife has the function of cutting, while
the heart has the purpose of pumping blood. Aquinas thinks that all substances
have final causes, but not all final causes are functions. For example, clouds
do have final causes, but not in the same way as artifacts or parts of organic
wholes.
In the broadest sense, the final cause of an object is an inclination or
tendency to act in a certain way, bringing about a certain range of effects.
For example, a knife is something that tends to cut, and a cloud is a substance
that tends to interact with other substances in the atmosphere in certain ways.
In summary, Aquinas' formal cause can be understood in three ways: the nature
or definition of a thing, the intrinsic form of a substance, and the final
cause of an object.
Aquinas' philosophical psychology focuses on the final cause, which is the
cause of all causes. He believes that an object's tendency to act in a certain
way requires a certain formal cause, such as being a thing of a certain kind
and composed of certain sorts of stuffs and organs. Some final causes are
intrinsic, meaning that every substance tends to act in a certain way, given
its nature. However, some final causes are extrinsic, meaning that an object
acts as an efficient cause of an effect partly due to the final causality of an
object extrinsic to it.
Aquinas also recognizes different kinds of knowledge, such as sense knowledge,
knowledge of individuals, scientia, and faith. For Aquinas, scientia is the
ability to understand an argument that is logically valid and knows the
premises of the argument with certainty. He believes that reasoning, the act of
drawing a logically valid conclusion from other propositions, is one of the
sources of scientia.
To come to know the premises of a demonstration with certainty, Aquinas thinks
that various powers and operations are necessary. He agrees with Aristotle that
intellectual powers differ from the sensitive powers such as the five senses
and imagination. However, Aquinas also believes that all human knowledge begins
with sensation, and even our knowledge of God begins with what we know of the
material world.
Aquinas argues that a comprehensive account of human cognition requires
mentioning various interior senses as preambles to proper intellectual
activity. Perfect animals, such as horses and oxen, must have a faculty that
senses whether they are sensing and unifies the distinct sensations of the
various sense faculties. This faculty is called common sense, and humans also
possess this faculty.
In addition to common sense, Aquinas argues that we need phantasy or
imagination to explain our experience of the cognitive life of animals,
including humans. Perfect animals sometimes move themselves to a potential food
source, and therefore, they need to imagine things they have never cognized by
the exterior senses. The faculty of imagination is distinct from the exterior
senses and the common sense, and humans are capable of imagining objects they
have never cognized by the exterior senses.
To explain the behavior of perfect animals, we need to posit two additional
powers: the estimative power, which perceives certain cognitions instinctively,
and the memorative power, which retains cognitions produced by the estimative
power. The presence of intellect in humans transforms the nature of these
powers, with the estimative power being called the cogitative power and the
memorative power called the reminiscitive power.
The cogitative power enables humans to make an individual thing, event, or
phenomenon an object of thought, while the reminiscitive power helps us
remember intellectual cognitions about individual objects.
Sunday, 2 June 2024
Aquinas and Epistemology
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Raymond Williams, "Modern Tragedy" (Book Note)
Raymond Williams’s Modern Tragedy offers a nuanced re-evaluation of the concept of tragedy by moving beyond classical definitions and situa...
-
The feminist economics project has made significant strides. This progress is particularly notable as feminist economics has transitioned ...
-
Armstrong's theory of the novel is distinct from Watt's, as she places greater emphasis on the history of female subjectivity and ...
-
The Process of Recording and Consumption • The process of recording and consumption is akin to the production of production, with the produ...
No comments:
Post a Comment