Arthur Schopenhauer was a
cosmopolitan philosopher who incorporated Hindu and Buddhist writings into his
philosophical system. He saw the world as a blind, purposeless, and irrational
will dominating the world, including humans. Schopenhauer's philosophy is often
attributed to his analysis of the self and the world as the product of an
irrational, unconscious, and purposeless drive called "will." He
argued that life is purposeless, with no ultimate goal or meaning, and that the
only way to escape from these torments is by "seeing the world
aright," acknowledging the pointlessness and insignificance of our own
willing existence. Schopenhauer's theory of perception and cognition moved him
away from German idealism and towards British empiricists like Berkeley, Hume,
Locke, Reid, and Kant. He used this view of the "intellectual" nature
of perception to argue for the ideality of the perceived world. Schopenhauer's
basic idea of the world as representation had serious consequences for the
reception of his thinking, especially in Anglo-American philosophy in the early
twentieth century.
Friedrich Schopenhauer, a philosopher, argued that the world is an object in
relation to a subject, as the subject is the supporter of the world and the
universal condition of all that appears. He distinguished his position from
skepticism, realism, and idealism, which he accused of making the object the
effect of the subject. Schopenhauer argued that subject and object necessarily
presuppose one another, and the law of causality applies only within the world
of representations and objects. He argued that all causality is only in the
understanding and for the understanding. Schopenhauer was inspired by Plato,
Calderón de la Barca, and Shakespeare, who describe life and dreams as pages
from the same book. He agreed with Kant that experience is dependent on the
nature of the cognitive faculties and that the world cannot exist independently
of the cognizing subject. Schopenhauer's arguments are not very convincing, as
he is right to hold that the representation of a world free from a subject
presupposes a subject but not that the existence of a world independent of a
subject also does. He also criticizes Kant's "Transcendental
Aesthetic" and his transcendental idealism.
In "Transcendental Logic," Karl Kant discusses the role of
understanding in our intuitive perceptions. He argues that our knowledge comes
from two sources: receptivity of impressions and spontaneity of concepts.
Schopenhauer criticizes Kant's vague use of terms like Anschauung, Perzeption,
and Wahrnehmung, and uses the concepts "perception" and
"intuition" interchangeably.
Kant divides objective perception into intuition (immediate) and concept
(mediate). Schopenhauer characterizes the understanding's activity as phenomenologically
"immediate" instead of inferential or discursive. In visual
perception, the understanding connects subjective sensations with an external
cause, creating a world of objects through the application of time and space
and the category of causality.
However, Schopenhauer's account of perception and the role of the understanding
is called for. He unjustly identifies subjective sensations with physiological
elements and fails to make clear how the manifold of light's affections on the
retina can provide anything like an "image." Paul Guyer argues that
Kant's transcendental method has been replaced by a phenomenological approach,
suggesting that sense impressions do not correspond with the objective
intuition of a world of physical objects.
Schopenhauer's hierarchy of the senses is remarkably close to Kant's, focusing
on the senses that Schopenhauer considers the "most noble" of all:
hearing and sight. He believes that the less noise one can bear, the more
intellectually gifted one is, and that the amount of noise we can bear is
inversely proportionate with intelligence. Hearing, along with sight, is the
sense of language and reason, the faculty of abstract reasoning, and distracts
great minds easily from their noble art of thinking.
Schopenhauer's theory of knowledge, aesthetics, and ethics emphasizes the
importance of sight and intuition in our experiences. He argues that sight is
the most important sense because it is not directly connected to the will,
making it the aesthetic organ par excellence. Schopenhauer's theory of
perception and cognition explores the concept of pure knowledge, which is
experienced through the senses. He argues that visual perception is the easiest
way to experience purely aesthetic pleasure, as it has no direct connection with
the will.
Schopenhauer's view of sight as the only truly objective senses is
controversial, as it threatens to disturb Schopenhauer's hierarchy of the
senses and seems to underestimate the sense of hearing. Additionally, there is
an unprecedented privilege attached to the transcendental form of space.
In Fourfold Root, Schopenhauer states that perceptions of sight ultimately
refer to touch, and sight can be regarded as an imperfect touch extending to a
distance and using rays of light as long feelers. This raises questions about
the nature of pure knowledge and the role of the senses in our experiences.
Schopenhauer posits that visual perception occurs unconsciously and is
accompanied by two systematic forms of "deceit": the illusion of
immediacy (time) and the illusion of the sensation itself giving us the objects
directly. The illusion of immediacy is strongest in visual perception and is
also the most deceitful.
Schopenhauer's theory of perception and cognition raises questions about the
nature of pure knowledge and the role of the senses in our experiences. While
he acknowledges the potential benefits of seeing and touch, he also
acknowledges the challenges and paradoxes associated with these concepts.
Schopenhauer's theory of perception and cognition posits that the intellect, a
physiologically linked to the brain, is an instrument of the will. He believes
that empirical cognition is driven by human needs, interests, and affects, and
that the intellect can be disturbed by the will. In aesthetic consciousness,
the "real self" appears to have vanished and is replaced by a
"better" or "higher" consciousness, which turns away from
the will and considers things as non-related to it. Schopenhauer distances
himself from the Western tradition's belief that intellect and reason are the
most perfect hallmark of humanity. Instead, he believes that cognition that is
not in service of the will remains possible, known as aesthetic cognition. This
state of awareness occurs when we perceive external objects and become
empirically aware of the world. Schopenhauer's aesthetic experience is
characterized by a state of extraordinary tranquility, where individual
striving, suffering, desiring, and worrying no longer occur. This heightened,
"objective" state of consciousness discards the embodied, willing
self and frees us from the pressures and torments of will.
Aesthetic perception, according to Schopenhauer, is a state of awareness that
transcends personal desires and offers freedom from the constant striving and
suffering. It is not just a heightened state of awareness but also a superior
form of cognition, as ordinary empirical cognition is guided by personal needs,
affects, and interests. Schopenhauer believes that aesthetic perception is a
sign of "the gift of genius" to attain and maintain a pure state of
dispassionate, "pure perception" and cognition.
Aesthetic, will-less perception, which Schopenhauer identifies with Spinoza's
notion of knowledge "sub aeternitatis specie," offers insight into
the timeless kernel of things, the universal essences of the perceived objects,
beyond mere appearance. These eternal essences are called the (Platonic) Ideas,
the "eternal forms" behind the mere appearances of common empirical
cognition.
Schopenhauer's aesthetics theory differs from Kant's view that aesthetic
judgment cannot be based on certain concepts. He argues that the forms of space
and time, and the understanding or intellect, ground and construct the world as
representation, characterized by plurality. However, his metaphysical view of
the thing-in-self is enmeshed in his claims, and his semi-Platonic account of
the Ideas is more Platonic than Kantian.
Schopenhauer's accounts of ordinary and aesthetic perception offer a critical
supplement to empiricist and Kantian theories of cognition and perception. He
suggests that the intellect is driven by human willing, and that aesthetic
perception allows the cerebral system to operate detached from the will. This
will-less aesthetic cognition is pleasurable, offering relief from suffering
and generating deeper insight into the timeless universals behind the mere
appearances of things.
Sunday, 16 June 2024
Bart Vandenabeele, " Schopenhauer on Empirical and Aesthetic Perception ...
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Raymond Williams, "Modern Tragedy" (Book Note)
Raymond Williams’s Modern Tragedy offers a nuanced re-evaluation of the concept of tragedy by moving beyond classical definitions and situa...
-
The feminist economics project has made significant strides. This progress is particularly notable as feminist economics has transitioned ...
-
Armstrong's theory of the novel is distinct from Watt's, as she places greater emphasis on the history of female subjectivity and ...
-
The Process of Recording and Consumption • The process of recording and consumption is akin to the production of production, with the produ...
No comments:
Post a Comment