Friedrich Schiller and Friedrich Schlegel were influential
in shaping aesthetics, literature, and criticism for centuries after Kant. Both
writers believed that freedom defines what it means to be human and that
literature is uniquely capable of embodying and expressing that freedom. They
both believe that literature is transformative, personally, morally, and
politically.
Schiller's conception of an aesthetic education centers around a holistic
notion of play, while Schlegel views Romantic poetry as a fragmentary
combination of wit and irony. Schiller asserts the liberating potential of
art's capacity to express the ideal satisfaction of human striving, while
Schlegel counters by asserting the equally liberating potential of art's
capacity to disillusion or remind itself that any such expression reproduces
the "endless play of the world."
Schiller's account of tragedy and its pleasure is framed by Lessing's
interpretation of sympathy and Kant's analysis of dynamic sublimity. He
distinguishes two sorts of sympathy in terms of what he takes to be the two
competing sources of pleasure and pain: sensual and moral. He acknowledges that
sympathy with another's suffering can be largely sensual, but to the degree
that moral capacities get the upper hand in someone, they are more likely to be
sensitive to the pleasure that, thanks to a connection with morality, combines
with even the most painful state.
Schiller links sympathy directly to our capacity for empathy, our ability to
put ourselves in someone else's situation, which requires in turn that we have
already been in the same sort of situation. The pleasure of sympathy is the
pleasure that derives from putting ourselves in a condition or situation in
which someone like ourselves finds herself and doing so in such a way that we
share in the action that is her moral response to that condition or situation.
Schiller also characterizes this moral struggle as something sublime,
contrasting representations of what is stirring and sublime from
representations of beauty. A sublime theme or object makes us feel the pain of
our impotence (Ohnmacht) on the one hand and exult at the existence of a power
in us superior (Übermacht) to nature on the other. In "On the
Sublime," Schiller revises Kant's notion of the dynamic sublime into the
"practically sublime," the moral neutralization of nature's physical
power over us.
Schiller's account of tragedy emphasizes the importance of power and a clash of
powers in portraying human phenomena that are contrary to or not determined by
instinct. The tragedy has the job of presenting both suffering and resistance,
or pathos and sublimity. The ethical propensity or "independence of spirit
in a state of suffering" can take two forms: negative or positive,
depending on whether a person's suffering has no effect on their moral
disposition or issues from their moral character.
Schiller distinguishes between sublime composure and sublime action, which
include both those who suffer for doing their duty and those who suffer for
violating their duty. He believes that the purpose of theatrical art is
pleasure and not moral improvement, and that aesthetic judgments have a more
liberating potential than moral judgments. According to Kant, the sublime can
determine the mind to think "the unattainability of nature as a
presentation of ideas."
Schiller's account of a sublimity beyond good and evil further embellishes his
explanation of the sympathy that the tragic stage calls for. We sympathize with
the moral potency of scoundrels, sinners, heroes, and saints, as it is the
capacity for a similar dutifulness that we share with them and the fact that we
see our own capacity in him that explain why we feel our spiritual power
elevated.
The art's capacity to "shape humans morally" is put great stock in
the dramatic artist's attempts to please. The greatest pleasure is accorded by
creating sublime characters with whom we can sympathize, protagonists caught up
in a moral conflict, because this sort of sympathy confirms and even enhances a
power within us as rational beings to transcend or overcome ourselves as
creatures of instinct.
Schiller argues that humanity is diminished in the arts and taste, and that to
solve the problem of politics, one must approach it through the aesthetic. He
rejects Rousseau's historical argument for educating humanity aesthetically and
proposes a transcendental path to a rational conception of beauty as a
necessary condition of humanity. He believes that every human being has an
enduring person and a transient condition, each dependent on the other and
demanding its due.
Schiller's notion of formal drive's connection with universal laws is inspired
by Kantian inspiration but takes cues from Fichte's conception of reciprocity
to elaborate a notion of freedom that requires coordination of both drives. He
constructs play as an experience where feelings and thought merge, stating that
man only plays when he is fully a human being.
In this aesthetics of play, beauty cannot be adequately understood in strictly
subjective or objective terms. Instead, it points to the subjective or
imaginative dimension of the human spirit, which enjoys complete freedom
relative to matter and form, passivity and activity, sensuousness and thought.
This will is grounded in the "mixed nature" of human beings and is
capable of being furthered or thwarted by natural means.
Schiller believes that the aesthetic condition is necessary for human beings to
move beyond the dismal state of nature and the demands of animal self-love.
Human beings are sensual and cannot be made rational until they have first been
aesthetic. The transition to the aesthetic condition is the most challenging
due to its emancipatory nature, which anticipates the moral condition.
Schiller introduces the concept of "the realm of aesthetic semblance"
or the "aesthetic state" in the Letters, highlighting beauty's
capacity to transform sexual desire into love and resolve competing desires in
society. In an aesthetic state, individuals can confront each other as free and
equal citizens, transforming into the third joyous kingdom of play and
semblance.
In his final major work in aesthetics, Schiller contrasts the naturalness of
naive poets with the more self-conscious and sentimental style typical of
modern writers like Ariosto. He traces the difference between naive and
sentimental poetry to antithetical modes of poetic consciousness, ancient or
modern, and even between contrary traits within a single poet (e.g. Goethe).
The central contrast lies in the fact that the sentimental poet alone calls
attention to a particular sense of the difference between reality and his ideas
and idealizations.
Schiller is less sanguine about the prospect of such a union than he is at the
conclusion of Letters. Underlying the poetic difference between the naïve and
sentimental is, he submits, a fundamental and debilitating psychological
antagonism resolved only in "a few, rare individuals" – the
difference between permitting nature (realists) or reason (idealists) to
determine theory and practice. Yet even on these final pages, Schiller remains
confident in poetry's paradigmatic capacity to reconcile basic oppositions.
In his early efforts to do for Greek poetry what Winckelmann had done for the
plastic arts of antiquity, Schlegel used "interesting" as a metonym
for "modern" and defined "interesting" as an unflattering
and ultimately incongruous characteristic of the goal of modern poetry. For a
certain stripe of modern aesthetes, Schlegel contends that it is more important
for art to be interesting than for it to be beautiful, even if what makes it
interesting is quite individualistic or subjective and permanently transient,
not least for the individual who initially finds it interesting. In this sense,
mixing genres and even mixing philosophy with poetry can make for interesting
art.
Schlegel, a prominent figure in the early German Romanticism movement, is known
for his fragment-style writings, such as his entries to Athenaeum. The journal,
which became the main literary and philosophical organ of the "Romantic
school," was the fruit of a circle of close friends including Novalis, the
Schlegel brothers, Caroline Schlegel, Friedrich Schleiermacher, Ludwig Tieck,
Dorothea Veit, and Wilhelm Wackenroder. Schlegel's most famous gloss of
Romantic poetry is "a progressive universal poetry." This universal
character lies in its refusal to identify poetry with any particular genre or
marks of a piece of writing that can be simply read off it. The sense of its
"universality" extends even further, as it aims to unite separate
genres and put poetry in contact with philosophy, making poetry alive and
social, making life and society poetic, poeticizing wit, and filling and
saturating the forms of art with matters of genuine cultural value.
The progressive character of Romantic poetry is tied to the fact that it is
self-reflective. Self-reflection is a transcendental notion in the Kantian
sense that it is the condition that enables every other consciousness
(unreflected or not, self-styled as poetic or not). For Schlegel, Romantic
poetry is not the antipode to philosophy; it is integral to philosophy's telos.
He criticizes the transcendental philosophies of Kant and Fichte for being too
linear and not sufficiently cyclical.
In his extensive work on fine art, dramatic arts, and literature, Schlegel
played a significant role in spreading the basic ideas of Romanticism across
Europe. His understanding of Romantic poetry incorporates various senses of
transcendentality, such as the relation between the ideal and real, and the potential
for reflection on that reflection or "progressive" self-reflection.
Romantic poetry can hover on the wings of poetic reflection, free of all real
and ideal self-interest, raising that reflection again and again to a higher
power.
Schiller and Schlegel share many similarities in their aesthetics, placing
philosophical speculation at the center of criticism and literature, drawing
critically on the transcendental philosophies of Kant and Fichte. They both
extol the distinctiveness of modern poetry and appreciate the moral and
political import of art and literature.
Friday, 7 June 2024
D. Dahlstrom, "Play and Irony: Schiller and Schlegel on the Liberating P...
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Raymond Williams, "Modern Tragedy" (Book Note)
Raymond Williams’s Modern Tragedy offers a nuanced re-evaluation of the concept of tragedy by moving beyond classical definitions and situa...
-
The feminist economics project has made significant strides. This progress is particularly notable as feminist economics has transitioned ...
-
Armstrong's theory of the novel is distinct from Watt's, as she places greater emphasis on the history of female subjectivity and ...
-
The Process of Recording and Consumption • The process of recording and consumption is akin to the production of production, with the produ...
No comments:
Post a Comment