Karl Marx believed that academic
philosophers were too little engaged with social questions and that philosophy
as a profession would never engage properly with the politics of thoroughgoing
social change. His interpretation of some of his works as philosophical or
stating philosophical doctrines developed in his later lifetime, and was the
work of Friedrich Engels, his lifelong friend and occasional collaborator.
After Engels's death, Marxism emerged as a comprehensive philosophy and
political practice through which many of the twentieth century's most important
social and economic transformations were envisioned and pursued.
Marx's early life has almost always been read as more aligned with reason than
with faith, although his parents were not radicals. His father encouraged him
to study at university, first at Bonn and then at Berlin, to become a lawyer.
However, open confrontations with the truths that were the bedrock of Christian
faith had to be avoided, and atheism or skepticism that would question the
tenets and position of Christianity was an obvious ground for exclusion and
dismissal in universities and the professions.
Historicization, a methodological thread in "free-thinking," was
derived from the late eighteenth century through German scholars' research into
ancient civilizations and languages. Both Strauss and Feuerbach proposed
versions of philosophy that would effectively transcend confessional
Christianity, at least for the educated classes where free-thinking had the
wherewithal to flourish. Friedrich von Schelling was appointed to the Berlin
Academy in 1841 to deradicalize the Hegelian legacy and discourage radicalism
among "Young Hegelians."
Karl Marx, a prominent German philosopher and journalist, participated in the
'48 revolutions in central Europe and emigrated to England in 1849. He worked
as a journalist and publicist for working-class political struggles worldwide.
In his autobiography, written in 1859, Marx presents himself as a social critic
and political activist, rather than a philosopher. He began his account with an
allusion to some of the few articles he wrote and published in his time as a
liberal journalist on the Rheinische Zeitung (Rhenish Gazette), a legal and
moderate paper in Cologne.
Marx's engagement with Hegel is framed as a detailed critique of the latter's
political philosophy as such, allied to a critique of his overall dialectic as
a general method. Marx's critical use of Hegel was not a simple reversal or
inversion, but rather a critique of the Hegelian philosophy of law.
Marx's political perspective on change and reform was more radical and
thoroughgoing than any adopted by political economists. He believed that mere
redistribution of goods and services would not resolve the social question of
inequality. Marx's engagement with any philosophy as such was secondary to or
explicitly in aid of his chosen political project, a politically motivated
critique of political economy.
Nineteenth-century socialism and communism were not consistently distinguished
from each other, but they comprised a wide variety of views on human nature,
ideal societies, and political tactics. Communists, such as Marx, were
generally more radical in focusing on working-class politics and calling for
large-scale, revolutionary change, using violence if necessary.
Marx's analysis of society, society, and politics is complex, focusing on the
relationship between humans and their relationships, such as property and work
relations. He links economic and political structures to the technologies and
practices through which production occurs, referring to this as a real
foundation. Marx believes that ideological generalizations are misleading and
selectively tendentious rather than enlightening.
Marx's outlook on history, society, and politics is summarized by asserting
that the mode of production of material life conditions the general process of
social, political, and intellectual life. He suggests four epochs in history:
ancient, Asiatic, feudal, and modern bourgeois society. Changes in social
formations have arisen from conflicts between productive forces and productive
relations, particularly when the property system restricts technological and
workplace developments that enhance productivity and innovation. Marx believes
that Bourgeois society will be under pressure from similar contradictions as
increasing productivity reduces employment and consumption, and the
dysfunctionality of a market system based on "private" ownership
becomes evident.
Marx's manuscript works of 1845-46, which were first published in part in the
1920s, have attracted the attentions of philosophers to an increasing and now
dominant degree. Engels, a prominent publicist of Marx, worked to make him
visible and gain political capital by making him a philosopher. Influential
works of the late 1870s and early 1880s, particularly Anti-Dühring: Herr Eugen
Dühring’s Revolution in Science (1878), were derived from unpublished notebooks
and manuscripts and produced with suitable flourishes by a Russo-German team of
Marxist scholars anxious to link Marxism with scientific certainty.
Marxist philosophy was initially marginalized by professional philosophers and
regarded with suspicion due to its purported political commitment to
revolutionary transformation of society. The Frankfurt School, established in
the 1930s, made early use of Marx's Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of
1844 and German Ideology, which had not been incorporated by Engels into his
Marxist dialectics and materialism.
Marxist philosophers in France and the Soviet Union applied Marxian notions of
social production, class structure, and ideological critique to cultural
criticism, social science, and historical research. Antonio Gramsci, a
Communist Party worker in Italy, argued against materialism of matter-in-motion
and instead favored a "praxis" account where intersubjective
categories of practical life and cultural understanding constitute the human
realm for political judgments. This approach to Marxism has been influenced by
philosophers and activists throughout history, including Hegel, Sartre,
Merleau-Ponty, and Lefebvre.
Postwar international political and economic settlements led to a significant
shift in philosophy practice and promotion. Marxist philosophers' political
commitment and interest in Marx's "theory of history" became
respectable, though not universally accepted. The continental tradition in
philosophy admitted Marx and his historicizing and Hegelianizing successors,
but not the dialectics and materialism promoted by Engels.
In the postwar period, Marx was re-read independently of Engels's systematizing
materialism and determinism, but in a more Hegelian manner. New texts, such as
the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 and the German Ideology
manuscripts of 1845–46, were suited to the construction of Marx's work as a
philosophy.
The philosophical "new Marx" was somewhat depoliticized in the
postwar period, with philosophers excited by Marx's terminology of alienation,
estrangement, species-being, and other humanist ways of setting out his
concerns.
The analytical school of Marxist thought, initiated in the mid-1970s by G. A.
Cohen, Jon Elster, John Roemer, Robert Brenner, and Erik Olin Wright, rejected
Hegelianism and the continental tradition as methodologically unrigorous. Instead,
rigor was identified with various presuppositions and methodologies, such as
individualism, propositional hypothesis, and clarity in language. Marx's role
in the philosophical debate was to resolve two significant puzzles: the
validity of his "guiding principle" and the validity of his theory of
exploitation. Analytical Marxists argued that Marx could be shown to be right
after all, while Roemer and others adopted strict assumptions from economic
modeling and game theory.
The "Marx and justice" controversy of the later 1970s and early 1980s
involved a wide range of Marx's texts, reflecting the increased availability
and respectability of standard and collected texts of Marx and Engels. Marx
praised Hegel for presenting basic human social institutions as historically
varied, malleable, and developmental, but criticized Hegel for a teleology of
progress and his view that human life and change were all ultimately a matter
of ideas. Marx countered that the universal human subject was the proletarian
or homo faber, "man the worker," who collectively would produce the
most decisive change in human history.
Hegel's dialectic is difficult to summarize, but Marx found it stimulating and
useful as a mode of critical thinking founded on assumptions of change and
development. Marx's twentieth-century reception of him follows Engels' general
outlines, which include materialism, idealism, and dialectic. However, Marx's
work has been rejected by postmodernists within the continental tradition of
philosophizing, who focus on historicizing the categories of consciousness
through which human experience is intersubjectively constructed and producing
language-centered accounts of meaning and communication.
The classic critique of both positions is that of Ernesto Laclau and Chantal
Mouffe, which counterpose Gramsci's flexible and contingent constructions of
cultural power to alternative readings of Marx, including Gramsci's own. Marx's
intellectual and political trajectory from 1842 was toward the social question
of class power and oppression, and his historical works appear as investigative
and exploratory, drawing out contradictions between events as he understood
them and his own generalizing theories.
Marx's relationship to philosophy and any continental tradition is highly
problematic at the outset, although there are affinites with other
antiphilosophical philosophies, such as Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951). Marx
was disinclined to find certainties in the commonplace antiskeptical small
change of ordinary life, as he argued that these are areas of mystification
where political power accumulates in the hands of the hands. His writings that
are taken to be of most philosophical interest were themselves produced as an
antiphilosophy, yet they were written in the terms through which certain
philosophies were articulated at the time.
Sunday, 9 June 2024
Terrell Carver, "Marx and Marxism" (Summary)
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Raymond Williams, "Modern Tragedy" (Book Note)
Raymond Williams’s Modern Tragedy offers a nuanced re-evaluation of the concept of tragedy by moving beyond classical definitions and situa...
-
The feminist economics project has made significant strides. This progress is particularly notable as feminist economics has transitioned ...
-
Armstrong's theory of the novel is distinct from Watt's, as she places greater emphasis on the history of female subjectivity and ...
-
The Process of Recording and Consumption • The process of recording and consumption is akin to the production of production, with the produ...
No comments:
Post a Comment