Jacques Lacan’s The Ethics of Psychoanalysis,
originally delivered as Seminar VII (1959–1960), is a powerful and complex
examination of ethics through the lens of psychoanalysis, structured primarily
around a reinterpretation of Freud, and enriched with references to Aristotle,
Kant, Sade, and Antigone. Rather than presenting ethics as a set of moral
injunctions or duties, Lacan explores the ethical dimension of desire,
subjectivity, and the unconscious. The seminar reveals Lacan’s commitment to
radicalizing Freudian theory, as well as his philosophical engagement with the
question of how one is to live and act in the face of the Real—what lies
outside the symbolic order.
Lacan begins by challenging traditional moral
frameworks. He distances psychoanalysis from both Aristotelian virtue ethics
and Kantian deontology. For Lacan, ethics in psychoanalysis is not about
achieving the Good or following moral law; rather, it revolves around the
subject’s relationship to their desire. The central ethical imperative he
proposes is: do not give up on your desire.
This is not an endorsement of hedonism or self-indulgence but a complex call to
confront the truth of one’s unconscious, even if it leads to discomfort,
sacrifice, or confrontation with the limits of the symbolic order.
Desire, in Lacan’s system, is not reducible to
biological need or conscious want. It is mediated by language, the symbolic
order, and the Other. Desire is structured by lack, and its object (the objet petit a) is never fully attainable.
The ethical challenge, then, is not to fulfill desire in a conventional sense
but to remain faithful to the truth it reveals about the subject. This
faithfulness entails facing the void at the center of subjectivity—the Real—and
resisting the temptation to retreat into fantasy or ideological comfort.
One of Lacan’s key innovations in this seminar
is the introduction of the concept of the Thing (das Ding), drawn from Freud’s Beyond the Pleasure Principle and beyond. The Thing is the
primordial object of desire, lost and inaccessible, representing the traumatic
core of the Real. It is what the symbolic system cannot represent, yet it
structures desire by its very absence. The Thing is simultaneously attractive
and terrifying, producing both fascination and anxiety. Lacan’s ethics revolves
around the subject’s proximity to this Thing, especially how one navigates its
pull without succumbing to either repression or self-annihilation.
Lacan also draws heavily on Sophocles’ Antigone to illustrate his ethical concerns.
Antigone becomes, for Lacan, the figure of the ethical subject par excellence.
She acts in fidelity to her desire—to bury her brother, even against the laws
of the city and at the cost of her own life. Her act confronts the symbolic
order with the absolute, exposing the limits of law, politics, and morality.
Lacan admires her ethical stance, not because it is noble or tragic, but
because it unmasks the Real and reveals the structural logic of desire. Her
gesture affirms a position “beyond the Good,” pointing to a space of radical
ethical integrity that is not reducible to utilitarian or normative frameworks.
In contrast, Lacan critiques the
Enlightenment’s moral philosophies, particularly Kantian ethics, for their
reliance on universal rational principles that ignore the unconscious. He also
provocatively connects Kant and the Marquis de Sade, arguing that Sade
represents the obscene truth of Kantian formalism. For Lacan, Sade’s fantasy of
absolute jouissance—pleasure beyond limits—exposes the latent violence and
repression inherent in moral law. Both Kant and Sade articulate positions of
ethical extremity, but psychoanalysis, according to Lacan, charts a different
path by situating ethics in the singular, divided subject rather than in
abstract universality.
Lacan develops the idea of jouissance—a term referring to excessive,
transgressive pleasure that often borders on pain—as a crucial ethical
category. Jouissance is what arises when the subject approaches the Real, when
the symbolic order breaks down. It is not pleasure in the ordinary sense, but a
traumatic kind of enjoyment that resists regulation. The ethical subject, Lacan
insists, must risk encountering jouissance without being consumed by it. This
requires a delicate balance: too much repression leads to neurosis, too much
proximity to the Thing leads to psychosis or perversion.
Lacan’s ethics is therefore about navigating
between these extremes. The analyst, in the psychoanalytic cure, is ethically
responsible not for interpreting in the name of truth or morality, but for
holding the space in which the analysand can come into contact with their
desire. The goal is not to heal in the conventional sense, but to produce a
transformation in the subject’s relationship to their unconscious, their
symptom, and their enjoyment. The analyst's position is fundamentally one of
non-knowledge, a refusal to impose meaning or morality, allowing the subject to
encounter the Real on their own terms.
The seminar also emphasizes the structural
role of fantasy in mediating desire. Fantasy serves as a defense against the
Real and provides a narrative framework for the subject to relate to the Thing.
Lacan warns, however, that fantasy can become a trap—a means of evading the
ethical confrontation with the truth of desire. The analyst must carefully
interpret and traverse the subject’s fantasy, enabling them to shift from a
passive position within fantasy to an active stance toward their own desire.
Lacan’s ethical vision ultimately opposes any
form of conformity, normalization, or compromise that sacrifices desire to
social norms. He is not proposing an anarchic freedom or unrestrained
indulgence, but a rigorous fidelity to the unconscious, to the singular truth
of the subject. His ethics demands courage—the courage to face lack,
contradiction, and the impossibility of full satisfaction. It demands a
recognition that ethical action is not grounded in the Good, but in the gap
between the symbolic and the Real.
No comments:
Post a Comment