The question of whether revolutionary violence is
justified demands a thorough exploration of the interwoven themes of
revolution, state legitimacy, and their relationship with violence. This essay
will articulate its stance on revolution and address the justifiability of
revolutionary violence. The argument will be grounded in the assertion that
revolutions, by their very nature, cannot be non-violent. The discussion will
delve into the definitions of violence, linking them to revolution, state
violence, and their impact on citizens. Throughout, references will be made to
the perspectives of Zizek, Fanon, and Marcuse, whose examinations of structural
violence, the necessity of violent uprisings for the oppressed, and repressive
tolerance form the foundation of the argument.
Attempting to justify or argue against revolutionary
violence is arbitrary. Such debates constitute a misunderstanding of the
essence and definition of revolution itself, as revolutions inherently involve
violence. There is ongoing discourse about the nature and definition of
revolutions, with scholars like Gilbert Achcar and Asif Bayat characterizing it
as "the rapid and radical transformation of a state driven by popular
movements from below," and Isaak Kramnick emphasizing its vision as
"a world restructured and regenerated in all its aspects." Slavoj
Zizek, on the other hand, sees revolutionary duty in the "assertion of the
unconditional, 'ruthless' revolutionary will" aimed at seizing power and
dismantling the existing totality. This essay adopts Zizek's definition,
viewing revolution as an absolute upheaval of socio-political and economic
orders within a society.
Since revolutions seek to bring about a complete
upheaval, a ruthless will, and a regeneration of society in all aspects, they
are inherently violent. Unlike attempts to make incremental changes within an
existing system, revolutions aim to overthrow the entire societal framework,
replacing old structures with new ones. Consequently, figures like Robespierre
and Lenin, with their goal of creating something entirely new, are perceived as
more violent than rulers like Saddam Hussein, who sought to maintain the status
quo through force. Zizek, drawing on Walter Benjamin, characterizes revolutions
as a form of Divine Violence—pure power over all life for the sake of the
living—an expression of the drive for excess life that strikes against the
"bare life" regulated by law, as described by Herbert Marcuse in his
critique of blind tolerance within the capitalist system.
Some examples of successful and legitimate revolutions
include the French Revolution and the Iranian Islamic Revolution. Examining the
French Revolution reveals its legitimacy as it led to the upheaval of an old
monarchic system from the grassroots, replacing it with a democratic structure.
While some argue that the French Revolution began as a call for economic reform
rather than radical change, the transformative outcome, where the commoners
became leaders, solidifies its status as a legitimate revolution. This view is
supported by the ongoing acknowledgment of the right of the French public to
protest and reform their government, exemplified by President Macron.
Contrastingly, the Egyptian revolution of 2011 during the
Arab Spring is an example of a non-revolution. Despite the initial uprising and
the ousting of President Mubarak, Egypt failed to bring about a comprehensive
restructuring of its society in various aspects. Described as a 'refolution'—a
revolution aiming for reforms within existing regimes—Egypt lacked a clear
ideology or future goal beyond removing Mubarak. The absence of partisanship or
a vision for the country's leadership and structure prevented any substantial
change, rendering it a failed revolution.
The confusion surrounding the term "revolution"
arises from its loose usage, encompassing any political change or unrest. This
misperception leads to questions about the necessity of violence when examples
of successful non-violent revolutions exist. The key lies in understanding what
qualifies as a revolution, emphasizing the restructuring and regeneration of a
state in all aspects.
To address the possibility of non-violent revolution, the
definition of violence must be explored. Drawing on Zizek's analysis, violence
takes two forms: personal (subjective) and structural (objective). Personal
violence is directed towards individuals and is often physical or
psychological, while structural violence is inherent in a system, sustaining
relations of domination and exploitation. This includes the more subtle forms
of coercion within a system. Zizek highlights the systemic violence of
capitalism, where the fate of populations can be decided by the speculative
dance of capital, perpetuating relations of dominance and exploitation.
Herbert Marcuse's essay on 'Repressive Tolerance'
provides a unique exploration of subjective violence, as elucidated by Zizek,
by examining the tolerance within society that allows violence to flourish.
Marcuse argues that this tolerance strengthens the tyranny of violence,
transforming into compulsory behavior towards established policies while
withdrawing it from any opposition, including political and revolutionary
opposition. This systemic tolerance perpetuates violence and suppresses
alternatives, resulting in the moronization of children and the mature
delinquency of an entire civilization.
One of Marcuse's significant assertions is that within a
repressive society, progressive movements risk turning into their opposite if
they accept the established rules. The exercise of political rights, in this
context, serves to strengthen the administration by merely testifying to the
existence of democratic liberties. This insight explains the failure of Egypt's
'refolution' and supports the argument that real change necessitates a
revolution, which, as demonstrated, cannot be nonviolent.
Understanding that revolutions cannot be nonviolent and
that attempts at nonviolent "revolutions" are merely progressions
within the same violent system, the focus shifts to exploring the legitimacy of
revolutionary violence. Zizek's analysis has already established society's
inherent violence, particularly against the lower working class. Thus, arguing
whether revolutions are justified leads to the realization that, in an
inherently violent system, revolution is the response to the repressiveness of
a tolerant society. To argue against revolutions would be to justify the
existing violence of the system. Society is already repressive, and upholding
the system perpetuates violence. Overcoming systemic violence, as described by
Zizek and Marcuse, requires real revolution—not peaceful protests, refolutions,
or progressive legislation but the divine, blind violence of revolution.
In conclusion, a clear understanding and definition of
revolutionary ideas are essential for making normative statements about them.
Acknowledging the existing violent systems shaping individual lives and societies
is crucial to understanding how to overcome them. If revolution is the only
means of overcoming these systems, then revolutions must be legitimized. Fear
of violence in revolutions dissipates when one is aware of the extent of
violence in the system. This essay has sought to examine what a genuine
revolution entails and explain why revolutions cannot be nonviolent,
establishing that revolutionary violence is always legitimate. It underscores
that delegitimizing revolutionary violence is a way of undermining revolution,
an erroneous judgment within a violent system.
No comments:
Post a Comment