Plumwood's book,
"Environmental Culture," presents a challenge to traditional ethics
and environmentalism by advocating for the development of an environmental
culture. Rather than proposing a theory solely focused on nature's moral
standing or a manifesto for environmental values, Plumwood calls for an ongoing
culture where ethical relationships with the biosphere are integral to human
flourishing. The urgency of this call arises from the potential entrenchment of
human recklessness towards the environment within various aspects of Western
and globalized forms of life. Plumwood suggests that our views on humanity,
rationality, science, politics, economics, self-health, relationships,
spirituality, and religion may all contribute to unsustainable environmental
practices.
Plumwood's book makes a valuable
contribution by addressing the need for cultural change and offering
suggestions for transforming aspects of our globalized culture. However, the
delivery is hindered by unclear arguments, jargon, and the tendency to make
sweeping empirical claims without sufficient evidence. Despite these
shortcomings, the book remains useful for its insights and challenges, even if
it lacks a robust argument.
The core of Plumwood's
argument revolves around the claim that what is considered rational within
global capitalism and Western culture is, in reality, irrational. Plumwood
contends that the prevailing form of rationality leads to self-destruction on
the planet, unethical treatment of the biosphere, and a failure to promote
human flourishing. The central idea is that rationality should promote
ecological relationships, and any form of reason that neglects or harms these
relationships should be deemed irrational. Plumwood emphasizes the need for a
shift in our form of life to embody an ecologically sound understanding of
human flourishing.
Plumwood critiques the current
understanding of rationality, drawing attention to its focus on maximizing
self-interest, human-centric ends, an ontological split between humanity and
the biosphere, objectification in scientific practice, and a lack of awareness
regarding place-based and interspecies relationships. However, her arguments
face challenges. Firstly, her characterization of rationality focuses on ends
and ontologies, deviating from the conventional understanding of rationality as
primarily concerned with means to ends. Secondly, the sources of this unified
notion of rationality remain obscure, with references to Cartesianism,
eighteenth-century political economy, capitalism, Christianity, and sexism
lacking systematic articulation and evidence.
Plumwood's empirical claims
about the destructive consequences of capitalism's rationality and the
unethical treatment of the biosphere are contentious and lack comprehensive
evidence. The distinction between unethical behavior due to human wantonness
and disrespect towards the biosphere could be clearer, as these aspects are not
adequately distinguished or interrelated in her argument.
In the introductory chapter,
Plumwood outlines two pivotal challenges crucial for the success of a
transition to an environmental culture. The first challenge is the
"re-situating of the human in ecological terms," while the second
challenge involves the "re-situating of the non-human in ethical
terms." Essentially, Plumwood advocates for the development of a human
ecology coupled with a non-anthropocentric ecological ethics.
As the book primarily
addresses the ecological crisis in contemporary Western society, one of its
main targets for critique is science. Plumwood contends that much of
contemporary science reflects a "form of monological and dualistic
thinking," where scientists distance themselves radically from the objects
of knowledge, denying these objects elements of commonality, mind, or
intentionality. This rationalist perspective leads to the objectification,
complete knowability, and technological manageability of nature, reducing it to
something replicable and replaceable. Plumwood argues that such thinking is
inherently anti-ecological, neglecting or ignoring humanity's
interconnectedness and embeddedness in non-human nature. She suggests that this
dualistic model of science is expanding, particularly with a significant
portion of scientists employed by corporations, turning science more towards
manipulation and less towards understanding, with knowledge acquisition justified
primarily by instrumental concerns.
Plumwood's critique extends
beyond social justice advocacy, encompassing a deep concern for non-human
nature. She presents an elaborate critique of anthropocentrism, arguing that a
radically rationalistic worldview bifurcates the world into separate realms of
active, knowing 'subjects' (humans) and passive, knowable 'objects' (nature),
resulting in a "radical discontinuity" between humans and non-human
nature.
She identifies four ways in
which this dualistic human-centeredness is fundamentally anti-ecological and
hubristic. Firstly, it justifies an ethics that does not extend beyond the
"human-species boundary," neglecting ethical considerations for
non-human nature. Secondly, human dependency on nature is downplayed or denied,
reducing ecology to a mere "technological problem to be overcome" and
fostering a false sense of human autonomy. Thirdly, nature is defined by what
it lacks in its non-humanness, becoming a purely negative space devoid of
culture, cultivation, and improvements. Finally, nature's independent agency is
erased, and its value is only assessed concerning human interests. Plumwood
argues that overcoming these "blindspots of centrism and human
self-enclosure" is essential for the survival of both humans and nature in
an age of ecological limits.
Plumwood goes beyond the
general feminist critique of dualistic conceptions of rationality, which often
focuses on the creation of hierarchies between opposed categories such as
masculine knowing subjects and feminine objects. Instead of merely discussing
dualisms as a failure to assign appropriate value to the denigrated, she argues
that ethical emphasis on value and rights perpetuates rankings, replicating
hierarchical structures and measuring all other life in comparison to humans.
Plumwood proposes a shift from the project of extending human-centered thought
to recognizing the value of others in relation to human worth. Instead, she
advocates for starting with basic respect for all life and approaching others with
an ethos of intentional recognition and openness.
Plumwood acknowledges that the
alternatives she suggests challenge the existing order deeply at various
levels. Her critical argument centers on the observation that prevalent
conceptions of rationality hinder the recognition of nonhumans as agents with
their own communication systems and ways of being mindful, different from
humans. Beginning with the belief that the other is potentially communicative,
Plumwood argues for an ethos of intentional recognition, emphasizing the
richness of communicative possibilities in the world. She encourages viewing
relationships with the world as dialogues rather than monologues, where
meaningful communication is not limited to humans or elite humans.
Throughout the book, Plumwood
emphasizes the irrationality inherent in what is often considered rationality.
She critiques the failure to appreciate the interconnectedness between humans
and the natural world, labeling it as a highly irrational response. While she
critiques specific modes of rationality, she relies on another understanding of
rationality to develop her critique. Plumwood presents a positive conception of
rationality as a form of life, emphasizing balance, harmony, and
reconcilability among an organism's identities, faculties, and ends. True
rationality, according to Plumwood, involves socially and ecologically healthy
decisions, acknowledging the embodiment of knowers, the contextuality of
knowledge, and the necessity of caring for flourishing.
Plumwood's work illuminates
how distortions in reason and culture contribute to life-threatening ecological
denial. In her multi-dimensional account of the crisis of reason, she reveals
the connections between culture's destructive practices, ethical and spiritual
shortcomings, and the failure to recognize ourselves as ecological beings.
Drawing from feminist thought, post-colonial theory, indigenous philosophy, and
extensive research, Plumwood provides a thought-provoking diagnosis of cultural
illusions contributing to the contemporary environmental crisis.
Environmental culture exposes
the anthropocentric logic of human self-enclosure, which masquerades as
rationality and infiltrates various cultural spheres. Plumwood argues that a
disembedded economic system collaborates with an instrumentalist, profit-driven
science, creating a reductionist form of science that deadens the natural
world. This reductionist science fosters illusions of power over nature,
contributing to conceptual blindspots and dislocation between production and
consumption. Political and economic systems normalize biospheric degradation,
suppressing critical reflexive feedback.
Plumwood challenges divisive
dualisms, revealing humans as ecologically embedded and nonhumans as ethical
subjects. She advocates for caring and life-affirming forms of rationality,
fostering inter-species dialogue and mutual flourishing. Her materialist and
place-based spirituality contributes to a critical political ecology. She
proposes an integrated, democratic, ethically responsive vision of science that
respects the agency of the more-than-human world. Plumwood advocates for
reducing remoteness as a political goal for ecological rationality, rejecting
eco-authoritarian solutions and promoting procedural and participatory
democracy.
She rejects the separation and
privileging of reason over nature, critiquing the delusion that human
rationality elevates us above the natural world. Plumwood emphasizes
ecosystems' interdependence and agency, advocating for an environmental ethics
of care. This moral framework aligns prudential and ethical treatment of
non-humans, emphasizing respectful and supportive relationships with the
natural world.
No comments:
Post a Comment