Deleuze's exploration of difference and repetition includes
both critical and constructive aspects. He criticizes traditional philosophy
for being trapped in a mindset that prioritizes identity over difference and
repetition. This tendency, which he calls the "transcendental
illusion," is deeply ingrained in philosophical thought and requires
ongoing critique to overcome. Deleuze aims to uncover this illusion and
demonstrate how it distorts genuine intellectual progress.
In contrast to this critical stance, Deleuze offers a
positive vision for philosophy. He suggests that philosophy should strive to
directly engage with reality by apprehending things in their unique
individuality. This notion of precision underscores his belief that
philosophy's goal is to grasp the essence of things as they truly are, distinct
from everything else. For Deleuze, difference isn't just an intermediate
concept but rather the primary aspect of philosophical inquiry, crucial for
achieving true understanding.
This pursuit of understanding echoes the longstanding
philosophical endeavor to grasp the essence of things, as seen in Plato's
dialogues and Aristotle's metaphysics. However, Deleuze contends that
traditional approaches, which rely on a simplistic notion of identity, fall
short in capturing the richness of individual objects of thought. Thus, he
advocates for a shift towards appreciating the uniqueness and singularity of
each thing, which he believes is essential for genuine philosophical inquiry.
Deleuze's examination of identity in "Difference and
Repetition" reveals its role as a tool for managing difference.
Essentially, identity functions by either grouping qualities or things as
identical across various instances or by dividing concepts based on contrasting
attributes. This approach, exemplified by Aristotle's genera and species model,
relies on defining essences or natures, which exclude contingent differences
such as those related to time, space, or individual cases.
Attempts to expand concepts to encompass even the most
contingent details, as advocated by Leibniz's principle of sufficient reason,
raise questions about the nature of concepts. For instance, if a concept
applies only to one thing, is it still a concept? Deleuze argues that concepts
typically designate a set of things with common characteristics, making them repeatable
and communicable. The challenge arises when confronting the singularity of
contingent moments in space and time, as exemplified by Hegel's critique of
sense-certainty.
Deleuze's critique extends to the notion of
representation, which posits identity as the central reference point for
thought. He contests the idea that thought's aim is merely to re-present what
exists non-conceptually, arguing instead for a disruption to the regular course
of affairs. While representation serves well in the realm of everyday
experience, where objects are recognized and ordered according to habit,
Deleuze sees it as inadequate for understanding thought, which involves
disruption and exception.
Deleuze's perspective on thought is dynamic, seeing the
thinker not as a passive spectator but as an active participant at the edges of
a system, initiating and revolutionizing thought. Thus, he challenges the
passive role assigned to the thinker in traditional representations of thought,
advocating for an engaged, dynamic approach to philosophical inquiry.
Deleuze contrasts the traditional model of thought, based
on representation through concepts, with what he calls
"dramatization." Instead of focusing on defining the essence of a
thing, Deleuze suggests asking questions like "Who?",
"How?", "When?", and "Where?" This approach,
often dismissed in philosophy as merely empirical, considers empirical examples
and circumstances as essential to understanding philosophical problems.
2
Deleuze draws inspiration from Plato's dialogues, which
he sees as dramatizations of central problems rather than straightforward
inquiries into essence. This contrasts with Kant's distinction between concepts
and Ideas. Concepts relate to our experience and form the basis of objective
representations, while Ideas guide our actions and are unattainable by
knowledge alone.
Deleuze sees thought as responding to problematic objects
or events that exceed our usual ways of understanding. These encounters provoke
us to engage all our faculties, creating a dynamic interplay between sense,
memory, imagination, and thought. The singularities of a problem—such as
"Who?", "How?", "Where?", and
"When?"—shape the conditions for its resolution.
In contrast to Hegel's emphasis on conceptual relations,
Deleuze sees thought as a response to unique events, not just a representation
of them. Thought emerges from the encounter with the unknown and creates
something new in the process.
Deleuze's notion of the Idea as a problem maintains
indeterminacy, both in the world and in thought itself. Thought confronts its
outside—the unthinkable—and is driven by this confrontation, without any common
measure between them. This absolute difference is the highest object of thought
for Deleuze, representing the challenge of thinking the unthought.
In Deleuze's view, the Idea persists beyond any
resolution, while the act of determination is subject to conditions,
particularly time. Time serves as the meeting point between the conditions of
thought and the excess of the Idea, highlighting their disparity rather than
their identity.
Despite the complexity of Deleuze's ideas, events in
thought aren't necessarily grand or historically significant. They can also be
imperceptible and subtle, akin to "little glimmers of the Idea"
beneath the surface of everyday happenings.
Deleuze's model of thought rejects the idea of a common
ground or shared reality that typically shapes the conditions of thinking and
communication. Instead, he presents thought as a solitary yet collective
activity. While he acknowledges the solitary nature of thought, characterized
by passionate individual engagement, he also emphasizes its collective aspects
and the importance of teaching and learning.
In Deleuze's view, the conditions of thought inherently
contain the principle of its continuation. Thought is dedicated to an ideal of
repetition, where each thinker and each thought reproduces the configuration
involved in the initial event of thought. This repetition is not about
reproducing the same, but about producing differences. Thought is transmitted
through a relay where the injunction is to repeat as different, with each
instance animated by the spirit of the first.
This form of communication, termed "rhizomatic"
by Deleuze and Guattari, spreads horizontally without a fixed origin or
end-point, unlike the hierarchical "tree-system" prevalent in
traditional philosophy. In this rhizomatic mode, each act of thought is a new
beginning emerging from contingencies, thinking with past thinkers as
contemporaries and companions.
For Deleuze, difference is both methodological and
ontological, meaning we cannot separate its being from its pursuit and
development. Thus, precision in philosophy involves determining the specific
context, conditions, and unknowns of a problem rather than isolating a
conceptual essence.
Despite acknowledging threats to thought, Deleuze
maintains an optimistic tone, focusing on the micro realm of the contingent as
a site of production and revolution. His commitment lies in affirming chance
and embracing the creative potential inherent in contingent events.
No comments:
Post a Comment