Bellamy Foster argues that
understanding Marx's materialist conception of nature is essential for grasping
his social thought. He highlights the historical influences on Marx's
materialism, tracing it back to ancient philosophers like Epicurus and Lucretius,
as well as English materialists. Foster contends that Marx's historical
materialism is deeply rooted in his understanding of nature, which he sees as
crucial for human self-consciousness, freedom, and progress.
The Western Marxism of the
1960s and 1970s shared a bias against naturalistic perspectives, which had
dominated social and cultural studies since the early 20th century. Foster aims
to resurrect a different Marxist tradition, tracing back to mid-19th-century
social and scientific thought. He suggests that Marx could have been a pioneer
of the ecological movement if not for two misinterpretations. One
misinterpretation arose from Western intellectuals like Lukács, Korsch, Adorno,
Horkheimer, or Gramsci, who viewed Marx through an idealistic lens, opposing
positivism and scientism. The other misinterpretation stemmed from a
mechanistic reading of Marx prevalent in communist Eastern Europe. These
interpretations obscured the "real" Marx, leaving him absent from the
early environmentalist discourse.
Foster argues that Marx was
rooted in the tradition of materialistic metaphysics, going back to Epicurus
and Lucretius, but this is widely accepted and doesn't need special emphasis.
Traditional Marxist thought emphasized the opposition between "idealism"
and "materialism," with materialism prioritizing matter in motion and
rejecting supernatural agents. However, this does not necessarily align with
"progressive" or "rational" tendencies. Materialism faced
challenges in explaining the emergence of life from non-living matter, as
spontaneous generation lost credibility with scientific advancements.
Materialist thinkers in the 18th century struggled to explain life without
resorting to vital forces or supernatural design. It wasn't until Darwinian natural
selection that materialism regained credibility by offering a mechanism for
self-organization.
Marx's adoption of a
materialistic ontological position was not particularly helpful heuristically,
given the challenges materialism faced at the time. Additionally, there was an
epistemological obstacle to Marx's understanding of society's relationship with
nature. Classical political economists, like Thomas R. Malthus, viewed land as
a limiting factor in economic growth. They argued that the finite availability
of land contrasted with the potential for exponential population growth,
leading to a stationary state where further economic progress would be
hindered. Malthus suggested that social reforms redistributing land would be
counterproductive, as growing populations would eventually deplete resources,
advocating for social stratification to maintain balance.
According to Foster, Marx's
belief in the eventual convergence of natural and human sciences stems from
this materialist perspective. He sees humanism and naturalism as interconnected
aspects of the same material reality. For Marx, communism represents the
positive abolishment of private property through collective association. Foster
suggests that communism, as fully developed naturalism and humanism, resolves
conflicts between humans and nature, and among humans themselves.
With Malthus, nature became a
powerful tool for conservative, anti-utopian arguments in political thought.
The idea of nature, previously invoked to support social reform in the 18th
century, now aligned with the status quo, demonstrating a harsh natural
equilibrium resistant to change.
Malthus, along with Ricardo
and other early 19th-century political economists, posed significant challenges
for social reformers and socialists. Marx's work on political economy can be
seen as a rebuttal of Malthus's theories. However, Marx couldn't simply adopt a
blindly optimistic view like Friedrich Engels, who believed in limitless
productivity through capital, labor, and science. Marx recognized the absurdity
of this notion, realizing that there must be limits to population growth.
As a materialist, Marx
acknowledged the validity of Malthus's argument about natural limits to
economic growth. Malthus focused on agricultural production, based on the law
of diminishing returns, which Marx understood in a changing context. Marx
incorporated insights from emerging sciences like soil chemistry, particularly
from Justus Liebig, to show that soil productivity was not fixed but influenced
by human activity. This shifted the perception of land and soil from natural
elements to products of human labor.
This shift had profound
implications. Classical political economy primarily studied agricultural
production within traditional energy constraints. Marx, however, witnessed the
transition to a new regime, where agriculture became dynamic and detached from
natural cycles. Soil was now seen as a resource that could be depleted and
replenished through human intervention, such as using guano or mineral fertilizers
processed with fossil fuels.
Foster argues that Marxist
materialism aligns with Darwin's evolutionary thought. Both offer
secular-scientific accounts of human development, emphasizing the importance of
historical and natural processes in shaping society and humanity.
Bellamy Foster emphasizes the
importance of the concept of metabolism in Marx's later work, seeing it as
central to understanding the relationship between humans and nature. He argues
that the alienation and exploitation of nature in capitalist society are
intimately linked to the alienation and exploitation of people. Foster suggests
that the metabolic interaction between humans and nature, represented by the
economic and ecological circular flows, underlies Marx's analysis of these issues.
Foster also highlights Marx's
ecological concerns, which were influenced by his criticism of Malthus and
Malthusian economics. Marx saw Malthusian ideas, which justified poverty and
inequality as natural, as a key ideological component of bourgeois liberalism.
Marx objected to Malthusianism for its unscientific basis, its defense of
aristocratic interests, and its disregard for the poor. Foster argues that Marx
sought to replace Malthusianism with a more scientifically informed
understanding of human-environment relations, drawing support from Darwin's
evolutionary theory.
Much of the evidence for
Marx's ecological perspective comes from his ongoing critique of Malthusian
thought throughout his life. Foster demonstrates how Marx's rejection of Malthusianism
influenced his views on human-environment relations and shaped his historical
materialism.
Foster's analysis of Marx's
ecological perspective has some notable shortcomings. While he argues that a
materialist-evolutionary view can support ecological concerns, he acknowledges
that Marx himself didn't place much emphasis on ecological sustainability
within capitalist society. Foster suggests that Marx's focus on issues like
capitalist agriculture and enclosures overshadowed his ecological considerations.
Foster also points out that
later Marxists, such as William Morris, were more explicitly eco-socialist,
indicating that Marx himself may not have been as focused on ecological issues.
Additionally, Foster mentions other Marxists like Bukharin and Lenin who
touched on ecological themes, but he admits that these ideas were not central
to classical Marxism.
Another issue raised by Foster
is Marx's Prometheanism, which suggests that a post-capitalist society would
rely on exploiting nature more rationally and intensively to achieve
superabundance. This perspective has been criticized as anti-ecological, but
Foster argues that such criticism doesn't necessarily align with anti-modernist
beliefs. However, Foster's discussion overlooks other critiques of Marx's
Prometheanism within eco-Marxist circles, which seek to reconcile Marx's ideas
with ecological concerns.
Foster acknowledges that Marx
and Engels didn't prioritize environmental concerns in their revolutionary
movement against capitalism. They didn't see ecological issues as central to
the transition to socialism, believing instead that sustainability would be
addressed after the revolution. However, Foster weakly counters the criticism
of Marx's Prometheanism by claiming that Marx showed concern for ecological
limits and sustainability in his texts, without providing enough evidence to
support this claim.
One aspect Foster overlooks is
Marx's strong faith in technological progress and solutions to societal
problems, including ecological issues. This optimism needs to be discussed, as
it forms the basis for ecological critiques of Marxism. Although Foster notes
that Marx and Engels didn't view animals as mere machines and rejected human
exceptionalism, he fails to address their ethical stance on non-human animals
and the natural world. This omission weakens their critical stance against
anthropocentrism.
No comments:
Post a Comment