Meikle's book Essentialism in the Thought of Karl Marx
serves a dual purpose: to argue that Marx holds an essentialist viewpoint and
to defend this essentialism. According to Meikle, Marx, like Aristotle, sees
entities such as plants, humans, or capitalist societies as organic wholes with
an inherent essence. This essence drives the entity towards its telos or final
state, which for Marx is the achievement of a free communist society.
Historical development, in Marx's theory, is propelled by human labor activity,
with class structures forming around this activity and either promoting or
impeding further development.
While Meikle acknowledges Marx's belief that historical
development is influenced by accidents, he argues that this does not negate the
teleological aspect of Marx's theory. However, Meikle's attempt to portray Marx
as an essentialist encounters difficulties. Marx's explanation of historical
development involves a complex interplay of necessary and accidental factors,
which is not entirely consistent with essentialism. Meikle's insistence on
essentialism requires showing that each society's future form is inherent in
its preceding form, but he struggles to demonstrate this in Marx's work.
Moreover, Marx's explanation of the capitalist wage-labor
relationship does not solely rely on the essential nature of preceding
societies. Instead, Marx considers various factors, many unrelated to
pre-capitalist commodity relations. Therefore, Meikle's effort to present Marx
as an essentialist results in an account of historical development that lacks
essentialist coherence.
In his analysis of Marx's essentialism, Meikle draws heavily
from the early chapters of "Capital, Vol. 1." Marx's discussion
traces the development of the finished value-form, which presupposes capitalism
and the capital wage-labor relationship, from its genesis in the elementary
commodity form. However, Meikle's interpretation is somewhat misguided. Marx
isn't detailing the historical process of capitalism's emergence from the first
commodity form; rather, he's elucidating the structure of the existing
capitalist system. He begins with the simple commodity form, devoid of the
capitalist wage-labor relationship, to explicate its structure more clearly.
Marx demonstrates how this simple commodity form inherently contains the
money-form, or how money arises from the commodity form. He then progresses to
illustrate capitalism's primary concern with money-making, depicted as M-C-M'.
Only after this initial analysis does Marx incorporate the capitalist-labor
relationship and continue his examination of the capitalist structure.
Meikle's interpretation is somewhat misled by the Hegelian
form of Marx's presentation, evident in his use of terms like
"genesis." Similarly, Meikle misinterprets Marx's critiques of
Ricardo in "Theories of Surplus Value." Marx doesn't fault Ricardo
for failing to provide a historical account but for misunderstanding
capitalism's structure. For instance, Ricardo's inability to grasp money stems
from his failure to comprehend its intricate connection with the commodity
form. Meikle is correct, however, in noting Marx's belief that once capitalism
is established, its development is determined by its essential form and will,
barring accidents, lead to communism. Yet whether Marx effectively demonstrates
this is debatable. Meikle's portrayal of Marx's views on capitalist
development, which are his own, is somewhat cursory, especially regarding
economic crises.
Meikle contends that Marx's labor theory of value logically follows
from his view of human history. He argues that since human labor and labor time
are fundamental to all historical forms, all historical categories, including
value, derive their essence from human labor. However, this assertion is
problematic. While it's true that all societies have concrete, useful labor and
a method for measuring labor time, it doesn't necessarily imply that the value
of commodities in capitalist society is solely determined by the quantity of
socially necessary labor embodied in them. Many economists, including Marxists,
have criticized the labor theory of value. Cohen, in his "Marx's Theory of
History," demonstrates that a Marxist theory of history, emphasizing
laboring activities, isn't contingent on the value theory. However, Meikle is
compelled to defend the value theory because his account of Marx's essentialism
heavily relies on it (albeit based on a misinterpretation of Marx's discussion
of the value form).
Meikle offers a basic discussion of the differences between
essentialism and atomism, mainly in Chapter 7 of his work. He characterizes
atomists as those who seek to reduce everything to simple building blocks
lacking complexity, often manifesting as methodological individualism in the
social sciences. However, Meikle's portrayal is somewhat simplistic, suggesting
that one must either be an essentialist or an atomist. This dichotomy is
flawed, as one can acknowledge the essential structure of capitalism without
subscribing to a teleological view of its development.
Essentialists, according to Meikle, believe in the existence
of organic wholes or entities with inherent essences that cannot be reduced to
their constituent parts. In the context of social sciences, this essentialist
perspective sees society as an organic whole with its own internal logic and
development. However, Meikle's argument overlooks the possibility of
alternative perspectives that acknowledge the structural integrity of
capitalism without attributing a predetermined telos to its development.
Meikle's attempt to demonstrate Marx's essentialism
ultimately falls short. Marx's discussions of historical development cannot be
neatly fitted into an essentialist framework. While there are instances in
Marx's writings that may seem to reflect essentialist tendencies, such as in
the early Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts and later in the Grundrisse,
Marx explicitly rejects essentialism in works like The German Ideology and The
Holy Family. These inconsistencies in Marx's writings pose a challenge to
Meikle's argument for Marx's essentialism.
Furthermore, Meikle's assertion that Marx's major work,
Capital, can be interpreted in ways other than essentialist underscores the
complexity of Marx's thought. While there may be elements in Marx's writings
that appear to align with essentialism, such as his emphasis on the internal
logic of capitalism, there are also countervailing arguments against a strictly
essentialist interpretation. For instance, Marx's analysis of historical
materialism emphasizes the role of contingent historical factors in shaping
social development, complicating any straightforward essentialist reading.
The question of whether these apparent elements of
essentialism in Marx's writings can be reconciled with his broader theoretical
framework remains unresolved. Meikle acknowledges the challenge of reconciling
these inconsistencies, particularly regarding Marx's early writings, but does
not provide a definitive resolution. It may be prudent to recognize the
presence of inconsistent elements in Marx's thought and approach his work with
a critical and nuanced perspective.
Meikle's attempt to demonstrate Marx's essentialism is not
entirely convincing. While there are elements in Marx's writings that may
suggest an essentialist problematic, there are also significant
counterarguments against such a reading. The complexity of Marx's thought and
the inconsistencies in his writings pose challenges to any straightforward
interpretation, highlighting the need for a nuanced and critical approach to
understanding his theoretical framework.
No comments:
Post a Comment