How Did Marx Invent the Symptom?
Lacan's statement that Karl Marx invented the notion of
the symptom may seem like a provocative statement, but it's not merely a witty
remark. Lacan suggests a pertinent theoretical foundation underlying this
claim, particularly in how both Marx and Freud analyze phenomena such as
commodities and dreams, respectively.
Marx's analysis of commodities aims to understand why
labor assumes the form of value in a commodity. Similarly, Freud's analysis of
dreams seeks to comprehend why latent thoughts take on the form of dreams. In
both cases, the focus isn't on uncovering a hidden content behind the form but
on understanding the inherent nature of the form itself.
Freud's interpretation of dreams has often been
criticized for its supposed pansexualism, especially when the latent content of
dreams doesn't seem overtly sexual. However, this criticism arises from a
misunderstanding of Freud's approach. The latent content of a dream isn't
necessarily sexual; it's a normal, preconscious thought that undergoes
transformation into the dream's manifest content through mechanisms like
displacement and condensation.
Freud's distinction between manifest content and latent
dream thoughts is crucial here. The unconscious desire, which is the true
subject matter of the dream, doesn't lie hidden behind the latent content but
articulates itself through the dream's form. Thus, the dream's form, not its
latent content, reveals the unconscious desire.
Freud's observations indicate that the form of a dream
frequently serves to represent its concealed subject matter. This paradox
underscores the notion that the unconscious desire expresses itself through the
dream's disguise of its latent content.
Freud and Marx both undertake a dual approach in their
analyses, emphasizing the importance of understanding both the form and the
content of phenomena such as dreams and commodities.
Freud first challenges the idea that dreams are mere
chaotic products of physiological processes, asserting that they carry meaning
that needs interpretation. He then directs attention away from the hidden
meaning of dreams to focus on the process of dream formation itself, which he
terms the dream-work.
Similarly, Marx challenges the notion that the value of
commodities is purely arbitrary, instead arguing that it is determined by labor
time. He then criticizes classical political economy for fixating on the hidden
meaning behind commodities, such as labor as the source of wealth, without
considering why commodities assume their particular form.
In both cases, the focus shifts from uncovering hidden
meanings to understanding the processes that give rise to these meanings. Marx,
like Freud, emphasizes the importance of analyzing not only the essence
concealed within the form but also the genesis of the form itself. This dual
approach is essential for a comprehensive understanding of phenomena like
dreams and commodities.
The unconscious of the commodity form
The Marxian analysis of the commodity-form, despite its
economic origins, has had a profound impact across various disciplines because
it provides a framework for understanding a wide range of phenomena beyond
economics. It offers insights into what can be termed as the "fetishistic
inversion" in society, which extends to areas like law, religion, and
more.
Alfred Sohn-Rethel, influenced by the Frankfurt School,
argues that the structure of the commodity-form reveals not only the workings
of political economy but also sheds light on the historical development of
abstract thinking and the division of intellectual and manual labor. He
suggests that within the commodity-form lies a sort of blueprint for the
Kantian transcendental subject, which consists of transcendental categories
that underpin objective scientific knowledge.
Sohn-Rethel identifies a concept called "real
abstraction," which operates within the social process of commodity
exchange. This abstraction involves the separation of a commodity's exchange
value from its physical properties and its reduction to a purely quantitative
entity, facilitated by money. This concept anticipates the abstract thinking
required for modern science and philosophy, showing how social practices like
commodity exchange shape our cognitive frameworks.
Moreover, the idea of "real abstraction"
challenges the traditional understanding of abstraction as a purely mental
process. Instead, it suggests that abstraction is external to individual
thought and is shaped by social practices and symbolic systems. This notion
aligns with the psychoanalytic concept of the unconscious, which encompasses
forms of thought that operate beyond conscious awareness.
Sohn-Rethel's philosophical endeavor presents a challenge
to traditional philosophical reflection by revealing an external place where
philosophical truths are already enacted. This confrontation exposes
philosophy's inherent blindness to this external place, which it cannot
acknowledge without undermining its own coherence.
Everyday consciousness, particularly during acts of
exchange, also exhibits a form of blindness. Individuals engaged in exchange
behave as "practical solipsists," overlooking the social dimension of
their actions and reducing them to individual transactions. This blindness is
necessary for the act of exchange to occur smoothly; if individuals were aware
of the true nature of their actions, exchange itself would cease.
This split between practical and theoretical
consciousness leads to a paradox: the non-knowledge of the reality of exchange
is integral to its functioning. Social reality relies on participants'
ignorance of its true logic. This dynamic illustrates the fundamental nature of
ideology: it is not merely false consciousness but rather the reality itself
that relies on a certain level of ignorance among its participants. In other
words, ideology is the social reality whose existence depends on individuals
not fully understanding it.
This concept resonates with the notion of the symptom,
which can be understood as a phenomenon whose very existence implies a certain
level of ignorance on the part of the subject. The subject can only
"enjoy" or maintain the symptom as long as its logic remains elusive.
The success of interpreting the symptom lies in its dissolution, revealing the
underlying truth obscured by ignorance.
Marx's notion of the symptom emerges from his critique of
bourgeois ideology, revealing inherent contradictions within its universal
principles. Rather than mere imperfections to be overcome, these contradictions
are constitutive of the ideology itself.
For instance, consider the concept of freedom. While it
encompasses various freedoms such as speech and commerce, it also includes a
paradoxical form: the worker's "freedom" to sell their labor.
However, this act of selling labor actually leads to the worker's enslavement
to capital, undermining the true essence of freedom.
Similarly, the idea of fair exchange in the market is
challenged by the emergence of wage labor. While pre-capitalist societies may
have achieved equivalent exchange, the universalization of commodity production
brings about a new form of exchange: the labor force itself becomes a
commodity. Despite the apparent equivalence in this exchange, the surplus value
generated by labor is appropriated by capitalists, revealing exploitation
within the system.
2
Marx's critique extends to Hegelian philosophy, which
conceives of society as a rational totality. Marx argues that any attempt to
view society as rational must acknowledge its inherent irrationality,
represented by the proletariat. The presence of this irrational element within
the rational framework of society exposes the contradiction at its core.
Lacan attributes the discovery of the symptom not to
Hippocrates, as traditionally thought, but to Marx. He suggests that Marx's
understanding of the transition from feudalism to capitalism is where the
concept of the symptom emerges. To grasp this transition, we need to understand
Marx's idea of commodity fetishism.
Commodity fetishism refers to the way social relations
among people take on the appearance of relations between things. For example,
the value of a commodity seems to be an inherent property of the commodity
itself, rather than a result of social relations between producers. This
misrecognition occurs because people see the world through the lens of
commodities and their exchange.
Marx's analogy between commodity fetishism and social
relations between people sheds light on this phenomenon. Just as commodities
seem to have inherent value, people's identities are shaped by their relations
with others. Marx compares this to how a person's identity is formed through
comparison with others, similar to Lacan's concept of the mirror stage.
In capitalist societies, commodity fetishism is
prevalent, but social relations between people are supposedly free and equal.
However, this appearance of equality masks underlying relations of domination
and servitude. This discrepancy between appearance and reality is the symptom
of capitalism.
In feudal societies, social relations between people were
more transparent, while commodity fetishism was less developed because
production was primarily for personal use, not for the market. But in
capitalism, social relations are disguised as relations between commodities,
revealing the underlying truth of exploitation and inequality. This discrepancy
between appearance and reality is the symptom of capitalism.
Marx offers a more radical critique than many of his
contemporaries who dismiss the concept of commodity fetishism as outdated. This
concept remains relevant in understanding phenomena like totalitarianism. To
illustrate this point, let's examine Umberto Eco's novel "The Name of the
Rose," which presents a flawed thesis: that totalitarianism arises from a
dogmatic adherence to official doctrine, lacking laughter or ironic detachment.
This thesis reflects an enlightened religious belief: an
excessive focus on goodness can lead to evil, especially when enforced
fanatically. But it overlooks a more unsettling reality: the possibility of an
obsessive attachment to evil becoming an ethical stance, as seen in Mozart's
"Don Giovanni," who chooses damnation over renouncing his evil deeds.
What's truly concerning about Eco's novel is its belief
in the liberating power of laughter and irony against totalitarianism. However,
in contemporary societies, both democratic and totalitarian, cynicism,
laughter, and irony are integrated into the system. The ruling ideology isn't
meant to be taken seriously; those who do are often marginalized figures. This
challenges the notion of living in a post-ideological society and prompts us to
define ideology more precisely.
At its core, ideology involves a fundamental naivete, as
Marx noted with the phrase "they do not know it, but they are doing
it." It signifies a misrecognition of social reality and its underlying
conditions. The aim of ideological critique is to make this naivete conscious
and dissolve it. However, contemporary society presents a challenge with the
rise of cynical reason, as described by Peter Sloterdijk. In cynicism,
individuals are fully aware of the gap between ideological masks and reality
but still uphold the mask. This differs from classical cynicism, which
challenges official culture through irony and sarcasm.
Cynical reason represents a kind of moral perversion
where integrity is seen as dishonesty and morality as profligacy. It
acknowledges the deception behind ideological universality but finds reasons to
maintain it. Traditional ideological critique is ineffective against cynical
reason because it already accounts for its own gaps and inconsistencies.
This shift to cynical reason might suggest a
post-ideological world, as Adorno proposed. Totalitarian ideologies no longer
claim truth but rely on manipulation and violence. However, this overlooks the
enduring influence of ideological fantasy, which structures social reality
itself. Cynical reason, despite its detachment, does not challenge this
fundamental level of ideological construction.
To understand the role of fantasy in ideology, we need to
reconsider Marx's idea that people "do not know it, but they are doing
it." Traditionally, ideology was seen as a misrecognition of social
reality, where individuals' actions didn't align with their understanding of
the world. For instance, in commodity fetishism, people attribute inherent
value to money, unaware that its value comes from social relations.
However, there's another layer to this illusion:
individuals are aware of the social reality behind money but still act as if it
possesses inherent value. They don't recognize that their actions are guided by
an illusion, a fetishistic inversion. This unconscious illusion, which structures
our relationship with reality, is what we call ideological fantasy.
In today's society, cynicism prevails, leading some to
believe we're post-ideological because people no longer take ideologies
seriously. However, ideological fantasy still shapes our social reality. Even
if individuals distance themselves ironically from ideologies, they still act
in accordance with them.
Sloterdijk's formula of cynical reason, "they know
very well what they are doing, but still, they are doing it," reflects
this. It suggests that individuals recognize the illusion in their actions but
continue to follow it nonetheless. For example, they might acknowledge that
their concept of freedom masks exploitation but still adhere to it.
Revisiting Marx's concept of commodity fetishism reveals
its subversive power in highlighting the relationship between persons and
things. Traditionally criticized by Althusserians as naive, Marx's idea
suggests that in capitalist societies, individuals interact with commodities as
if they have inherent value, despite knowing otherwise. This inversion, where
things believe in their place instead of the subjects, is akin to a Lacanian
proposition.
According to Lacan, belief is not solely an internal
phenomenon but is embodied in practical actions. This externalization of belief
can be seen in various cultural practices, such as Tibetan prayer wheels or
canned laughter in television shows. In both cases, individuals delegate their
emotional responses to external entities, fulfilling social duties through
them.
The objective status of belief becomes evident in these
examples, emphasizing the role of external factors in shaping our perceptions
and behaviors. Ignoring this objective dimension of belief can lead to
misunderstandings, as illustrated in the anecdote of the man who believed he
was a grain of corn. Thus, acknowledging the externalization of belief is
crucial for understanding how individuals engage with ideology.
The key takeaway here is that belief is not merely an
internal state but is manifested in our social activities, supporting the
fantasy that governs social reality. Using Kafka's work as an example, we can
see that what appears as an exaggeration or distortion of reality is actually
an expression of the underlying fantasy shaping social interactions.
In our society, certain beliefs, such as the power of
bureaucracy or the authority of political figures, influence our behavior even
though we may consciously acknowledge their limitations. This differs from the
traditional approach to ideology, which focuses on analyzing the ideological
form of society based on its social relations. Instead, an analytical approach
should prioritize understanding the ideological fantasy operating within social
reality itself.
Social reality is constructed ethically, based on a
collective "as if" belief in certain ideas or institutions. Pascal's
concept of Ideological State Apparatuses highlights this, suggesting that our
internal reasoning is influenced by external symbolic networks, leading us to
obey authority not because it is just, but because it is accepted. This
underscores the external nature of belief, which is embodied in our social
functioning.
3
For Pascal, obedience to the law is not based on rational
argumentation but on ideological ritual. This mirrors the Marxist notion of
ideological conversion, where individuals, unable to believe in the historical
mission of the working class due to bourgeois prejudices, must immerse
themselves in revolutionary activities to foster belief. This process of
external obedience ultimately leads to internal conviction.
The significance of Pascal's concept lies in the
paradoxical nature of belief: individuals believe without consciously knowing
it, and their final conversion is merely a formal acknowledgment of what they
have already believed. This underscores the role of external customs as
material supports for the unconscious. Films like "Another Country"
sensitively depict this process of "believing without knowing it,"
particularly in the context of conversion to Communism.
The film "Another Country" explores the
relationship between two Cambridge students, one being the Communist Judd
(based on John Cornford) and the other, the wealthy Guy Bennett, who later
becomes a Russian spy (based on Guy Burgess). Despite no sexual relationship
between them, Guy's charm doesn't affect Judd, making him the focus of Guy's
transference.
Set in the 1930s public school environment, the film
exposes the facade of patriotism and the underlying atmosphere of enjoyment,
particularly through a network of homosexual relationships. This atmosphere,
filled with tension and enjoyment, attracted KGB recruiters, offering an escape
from the pressure through renunciation.
Guy's conversion is depicted delicately in the film,
leaving out the formal act but indicating its elements. His tension leads him
to recognize the key to his situation lies in his relationship with Judd.
Despite Guy's reproaches to Judd's inconsistencies and revealing the mechanism
of transference, he remains trapped in it, as his accusations gain meaning only
in the context of their relationship.
The tension reaches its peak as Guy realizes the gap
between the mask and the truth, leading to his escape into belief in Communism
and espionage, creating a radical gap between appearance and reality. The film
ends with Guy already a believer, though unaware, as he muses on the
possibility of Communism's truth.
Drawing on Kafka's work, the film highlights the gap
between the bureaucratic "machine" and its internalization. Kafka's
irrational bureaucracy represents the ideological state apparatus confronting
subjects before identification occurs, emphasizing the role of ideological
fantasy in shaping reality.
In Lacanian terms, reality is constructed to avoid
confronting the Real of desire. The dream in the film serves to prolong sleep,
but the encounter with the Real of desire is too terrifying, leading to
awakening. This underscores the function of reality as a fantasy construction
to mask the Real.
In essence, ideology isn't merely a dreamlike illusion we
create to escape harsh reality. Instead, it's a fantasy construction that forms
the basis of our perception of reality itself. It serves as a support for our
understanding of social relations, masking some uncomfortable truths or
contradictions within society.
Lacan's interpretation of Zhuang Zi's dream of being a
butterfly highlights this idea. While awake, Zhuang Zi could question whether
he was truly himself or the butterfly, but in the dream, this reflection wasn't
possible. This asymmetry illustrates how the dream state, where our desires are
expressed, offers a closer glimpse of reality than our waking state.
Similarly, ideology functions to shape our understanding
of reality, even when faced with contradictory evidence. For example, in
anti-Semitism, even if factual evidence contradicts the stereotype of Jews, the
ideology may twist this contradiction to reinforce itself.
Contrary to Marxism, which emphasizes historical and
class-based analysis of ideology, Lacanian theory focuses on the internal
contradictions within ideology itself. It suggests that attempts to historicize
or universalize certain phenomena, like the patriarchal family or concentration
camps, can obscure the underlying truth that resurfaces across different
historical contexts.
Marx's concept of surplus-value aligns with Lacan's idea
of surplus-enjoyment, highlighting how capitalism's inherent contradictions
lead to its own limits. This notion suggests that ideology, like capitalism,
contains its own internal contradictions that shape our perception of reality.
The formula "the limit of capital is capital
itself" can be interpreted in two ways. The traditional
historicist-evolutionist interpretation views it as the dialectics between
productive forces and relations of production. According to this view,
capitalism develops productive forces until they outgrow existing social
relations, leading to the need for revolutionary change.
However, Marx's analysis goes beyond this simplistic
view. He distinguishes between formal and real subsumption of production under
capitalism, showing that capitalism initially adapts existing production
processes before reshaping them to fit its needs. Thus, it's not merely the
relations of production constraining further development but the internal
contradiction inherent in capitalism itself.
Unlike previous modes of production, capitalism is marked
by a perpetual contradiction between social production and private
appropriation, driving it towards constant development. This contradiction
fuels capitalism's need for continuous revolutionizing of its conditions of
existence. Surplus-enjoyment, akin to surplus-value in Marx's theory, emerges
from this inherent imbalance, constituting the excess that sustains
capitalism's dynamism.
Despite Marx's insights, his formulation in the Critique
of Political Economy often lapses into a vulgar evolutionist dialectic,
portraying socialism as the solution to capitalism's contradictions. However,
history's irony lies in the emergence of "real socialism," which
reproduces this evolutionary logic and fails to address the paradoxes of
surplus-enjoyment.
No comments:
Post a Comment