Ancient Aesthetics: A
Question of Compatibility and Challenges
The Concept of Ancient Aesthetics
• Ancient aesthetics emerged in the 18th century, making it an anachronism to
discuss ancient Greek and Roman aesthetics.
• Oskar Kristeller, an influential critic, argued that ancient aesthetics was
not a philosophical discipline due to its focus on moral, religious, and
practical aspects of art.
• Kristeller's critique is still relevant in works dealing with ancient ideas
on arts and beauty.
Criticism of Kristeller's Interpretation
• Stephen Halliwell criticized Kristeller's argument, arguing that the concept
of mimesis was a more unified concept of art than Kristeller allows.
• James Porter criticized Kristeller's premises and conclusions, arguing that
the concept of fine arts does not indicate the emergence of aesthetic theory.
• Plato and Aristotle's ideas are relevant to modern philosophers and address
foundational questions of aesthetics and philosophy of art.
The Translation and Conceptualization of the term to Kalon
• The term to kalon (honestum in Latin) has ambiguous meanings, ranging from
'beauty' to 'being appropriate.'
• Early 21st-century thinkers argue that to kalon and similar Greek and Latin
terms should be read as aesthetic concepts.
• Some studies argue that the conceptualisation and translation of the term
depend on the context in which it is found.
Three Types of Theories about the Origin of Beauty
• Proportion: The idea that beauty originates from the proportion of the parts
of an object is one of the most straightforward ways of accounting for beauty.
• Polycleitus, a sculptor, is usually credited with the idea that beauty
derives from summetria, meaning good, appropriate or fitting proportionality.
Philosophical Perspectives on Numbers and Beauty
Pythagoreans
• The Pythagoreans, active in the 5th and 4th centuries B.C.E., believed that
numbers underlie the world's ontological and epistemological structure.
• They argued that everything in the world can be explained in terms of numbers
and their relationship, namely, proportion.
• They used beauty as a property to support their doctrine, claiming its
presence can be fully explained in terms of numbers or the proportion and
harmony expressed in numerical relationships.
• Sextus Empiricus recorded the Pythagorean argument that sculpture and
painting achieve their ends by means of numbers, and thus art cannot exist
without proportion and number.
Music
• The Pythagoreans had a well-known interest in music, with Pythagoras being
the first to pinpoint the mathematics underlying the Greek music scale.
• Music is said to have a positive influence on a person’s soul, comparable to
the effect that medicine has on a person’s body.
Plato and Aristotle
• Plato is best classified as a Form Theorist, but a few passages suggest a
viewpoint derived from summetria, or a good proportion or ratio of parts.
• In the Timaeus, lacking summetria is associated with lacking beauty.
• Aristotle named summetria one of the chief forms of beauty, alongside order
and definiteness.
• Aristotle also claimed that size was also necessary for beauty, as seen in
Nicomachean Ethics 4.3.
The Stoics
• The Stoics defined beauty as originating from the summetria of parts with
each other and with the whole.
• This definition applies to both the beauty of the body and the beauty of the
soul.
• The Stoics often invoked the notion of functional beauty, likely a
combination of functional and proportion theories.
Functional Theory in Ancient Philosophy
Xenophon's Functional Theory
• Xenophon's Memorabilia presents a functional theory of beauty.
• Socrates argues that beauty is dependent on the same things that men use,
such as functionality.
• The term "to kalon" is used to describe functionality, suggesting
that pleasure is gained from perceiving functionality rather than pleasing,
artificial colors and structures.
Hippias Major's Functional Definition of Beauty
• Socrates proposes a functional definition of beauty in his dialogue with
Hippias.
• He presents two cases where a beauty-making property is not inherent to an
object but its functionality.
• This rejection of Hippias' suggestion that beauty is gold is based on the
fact that beauty is not inherent but rather derived from functionality.
Aristotle's Functional Theory
• Aristotle's work describes excellence in functionality through the term
"to kalon."
• He states that fitting a function and to kalon are the same, indicating that
fitting a function and to kalon are the same.
• Aristotle's descriptions of natural phenomena, such as the generation of bees
and the prospect of eating rabbits, provide pertinent passages for
functionalist understanding of aesthetic properties.
The Stoics' Functional and Aesthetic Language
• Panaetius uses the term "to prepon" in ethical arguments, comparing
poetry and human behavior.
• Panaetius argues that humans are functional entities with a certain function
and end, and that achieving that end produces beauty.
Plato's Theory of Forms and Aesthetics
• Plato's theory of forms posits that universal, ideal paradigms, or forms, are
the cause of aesthetic properties.
• Beauty, like many other properties, is generated by its respective form.
• The form of Beauty is mentioned as the cause of beauty throughout the
Platonic corpus.
• The form of Beauty has a special connection with the form of Good, even if
they are not identical.
• The acquisition of knowledge, or the knowledge of the forms, is represented
as the Ladder of Love.
• The form of Beauty is everlasting, unchanging, and not only beautiful at one
point but ugly at another.
Plotinus' View on Beauty
• Plotinus, a follower of Plato, also believed that beauty originated from the
form of Beauty.
• He argued that the Intellect (nous) is the cause of beauty, imposing forms
onto passive matter and producing beauty.
• Forms unify disarrayed and chaotic elements into harmony, producing beauty
that 'communicates itself' to both parts and the whole.
• Plotinus' metaphysics and aesthetics converge in the analogy between
Intellect shaping the universe and a sculptor shaping a piece of stone into a
statue.
• The beauty of the actual forms is purely intellectual,'seen' with the mind’s
eye.
Plotinus and Plato's Views on Artistic Beauty
• Plotinus and Plato both argue that visible beauty is inferior, but Plotinus
warns against devaluing artistic activities.
• Plotinus argues that nature imitates some things, and arts do not simply
imitate what is seen by the eye but refer back to the principles of nature.
• Arts produce many things not by copying, but from themselves. They add what
is lacking, because arts contain beauty themselves.
Philosophy of Art
• Mimesis, a term for imitation in art, is a widely used term in Greek thought.
• Mimesis refers to imitation in a broad sense, including acts such as
following an example of someone’s behavior or adopting a certain custom.
• Aristotle grouped poetry with “the other mimetic arts” in the Poetics,
suggesting a distinct group of artistic activities resembling the notion of
fine arts.
Plato’s Republic Analysis of Mimesis
• Socrates and the interlocutors agree to ban certain stories based on their
content from the guardians’ education and the ideal city-state.
• Socrates distinguishes direct speech from imitative speech, suggesting that a
poem in the former style contains no mimesis.
• The discussion turns to the question of whether mimetic poets ought to be
allowed into the city-state and whether guardians themselves could be mimetai.
• The main argument against mimesis in the ideal city is that the guardians
should imitate the properties of virtue, not shameful or slavish acts.
• Only a pure imitator of a good person should be allowed into the city-state.
Aristotle's Perspective on Poetry and Criticism of Arts
Aristotle's Theory of Poetry
• Poetics originates from human nature's natural inclination to mimesis, a
method of learning from childhood and a source of delight.
• People delight in artistic depictions of objects, either because they
recognize the person depicted or admire the execution, color, etc.
• This principle applies not only to visual arts but also to poetry due to the
natural inclination to mimesis combined with the sense of harmony and rhythm.
Differences Between Poetry and History
• Poets differ from historians by describing what might happen, not what
happened.
• The difference lies in the focus of the former on statements about
particulars, while the latter is concerned with universal statements.
• Some tragedies use historical characters, but this is because “what is
possible is credible.”
• The poet is a poet because of the plot rather than the verse, as the defining
characteristic of such activity is the imitation of action.
Critique of Arts by Plato
• Plato saw potential dangers associated with mimetic activities.
• He argued that the products of artistic activities are twice removed from
what is actually the case.
• Plato's theory of art is more complex, with criticism being only one aspect
of his treatment of artistic mimesis.
• Socrates suggests an analogy between the ideal political state and an idealised
portrait, arguing that there is more to painting than the copying of
appearances.
• Socrates also praised Homer, who is said to be the best of the tragedians,
and made concessions for hymns to god and eulogies to good people.
Epicurean Perspective on Poetry and Art
• Epicureans, a Hellenistic philosophical school, were critical of poetry,
particularly the atomist physics and hedonist ethics.
• Epicurus, the founder of the school, criticized muthos, stories told by
poets, for their potential to instill anxiety in listeners.
• He argued against traditional education, including poetry, but did not oppose
poetry or arts.
• Lucretius, the author of the Epicurean epic poem De Rerum Natura, viewed
poetry differently, arguing that only an Epicurean would discuss music and
poetry correctly.
Catharsis and Sublime
• Catharsis is a psychological phenomenon often associated with the effects of
art on humans.
• Aristotle described catharsis in Poetics and Politics, highlighting its
influence on emotions and judgements.
• The concept of catharsis has both religious and medical connotations, but
recent interpretations suggest it is primarily a psychological phenomenon with
ethical aspects.
Sublime
• The term "sublime" originated in antiquity and was later adopted by
Kant and Burke.
• The main source for the theory of the sublime is the handbook on oratory
titled Peri Hupsous.
• Longinus describes the sublime as a property of style, "certain
loftiness and excellence of language."
• Longinus suggests that sublimity originates from five sources: the greatness
of thought, a vigorous treatment of passions, skill in employing figures of
thought and speech, dignified expressions, and majesty and elevation of
structure.
No comments:
Post a Comment