Kant's work in 1781 marked a significant turning point in
the history of philosophy. His first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason
introduced a "critical" philosophy with a radical new approach to
traditional questions in epistemology and metaphysics, completely reshaping the
philosophical landscape. He would produce significant and original
contributions to philosophical ethics in his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of
Morals (1785), Critique of Practical Reason (1788), and the second part of his
Metaphysics of Morals (1797).
Kant's early works are commonly referred to as "precritical
writings," which give little hint of the scope, originality, and
significance of the work that followed. Born into a modest atmosphere
influenced by Pietism, Kant was strongly influenced by theology professor Franz
Albert Schultz and philosophy professor Martin Knutzen, who took seriously the
work of Leibnizian Christian Wolff. Other prominent influences included
Aristotelian philosophy and Christian Thomasius's eclecticism.
Kant's earliest publications deal with questions at the intersection of natural
science and philosophy and on methodological issues in philosophy and theology.
His first book, Th oughts on the True Estimation of Living Force, written in
1746 and published in 1749 when Kant was still a young student, and his
dissertation Succinct Exposition of Some Meditations on Fire and his General
History of Nature and Theory of the Heavens from the same year are examples of
the former. Prime examples of the latter include his 1755 essay A New
Exposition of the First Principles of Metaphysical Knowledge, his essay on The
Only Possible Basis of a Demonstration of the Existence of God, his
Investigations of the Clarity of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morals,
and the inaugural dissertation On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and
the Intelligible World, which he defended in conjunction with his appointment
to the rank of professor in 1770.
Much of the Critique hinges on Kant's analysis of the notion of
"experience" itself. He tries to show that experience involves more
than just having sense impressions, and that positive knowledge is possible
only on the basis of experience, which necessarily involves both sense
experience (intuitions) and the operations of the intellect (concepts). Kant
distinguishes between those functions of the mind involved in the organization
and unification of intuitions into knowledge from the functions that involve
the higher-order unifying operations of seeking overarching unities or ultimate
grounds for knowledge in objects that lie outside the realm of sense
experience.
Kant's primary focus is on reason only in its theoretical function, that is, in
its claims to knowledge. He concludes that the intellect in conjunction with
the senses can provide us with more or less reliable, empirical knowledge of
sense objects, but that reason alone cannot yield theoretical knowledge.
Kant's philosophy emphasizes the importance of understanding the categories of
thought and the role of concepts in recognizing and organizing the material
provided by intuition. He presents twelve categories of thinking that
correspond to the forms of judgment: quantity (universal, particular, or
individual), quality (reality, negation, limitation), relation (inherence and
substance, cause and effect, mutual interaction), and modality (possibility,
actuality, necessity). These categories are called the "metaphysical
deduction" of the categories and are necessary conditions for the
possibilities of experience and any object of experience for us.
Kant argues that experience, objects of experience, and even the consciousness
of the subjects who experience objects are unities, not just aggregates of data
that come and go over time. Each of these categories has a fundamental unity
across time in spite of the specific changes in the state of experience, in
objects, and in the subjects of experience over time. Knowledge involves
recognition of patterns and the assumption that there are patterns within
experience. The fact that we must assume that we can and do organize our
intuitions according to these patterns for knowledge to be possible is the core
insight that Kant advances in these sections.
However, the general arguments about the nature and necessity of the categories
leave open the question of how specific they apply to objects. Kant's
philosophy and approach to understanding nature involve identifying three
categories of relation: substance, causality, and modality. The categories of
relation have temporal schemata, such as simultaneity according to substance
and succession according to causality. Modality is characterized by its
relationship to the conditions of experience, such as possibility, actuality,
and necessity.
Attaining knowledge involves organizing the material provided by the senses
according to the general rules of what things are "always" given
together or "always" succeed each other. Intuition provides not only
the raw material for knowledge but also a guide for how to arrange them in terms
of their formal temporal relationships and the measure and corrective of
empirical knowledge through what Kant calls the "further course of
experience." Empirical knowledge is always open to revision because the
rules that we are attempting to discern through the course of specific
experiences given to us are intended as holding "always."
Kant's philosophy has been criticized for its close tie to modern natural
science, its focus on "objectivity," and its narrow notion of human
cognition. Subsequent developments in mathematics and natural science raise the
question whether Kant's orientation on Euclidean geometry and Newtonian physics
as paradigms of knowledge is evidence that his universal and unchangeable a
priori principles are actually assumptions that hold only relative to these
specific systems.
The Critique of Pure Reason by Augustus Kant is a philosophical treatise that
argues that philosophy can identify a priori, nonempirical, or
"metaphysical" principles for practical reason. Kant's moral theory
begins with an analysis of common intuitions about the nature of moral
obligation, asserting that there is nothing in the world that could be
considered good without any qualification except for a good will. He defines
"duty" as the necessity of an action done out of respect for the law.
Kant's answer to everyday common sense is that all of us experience cases where
our inclinations conflict with what we know we ought to do (our duty). We
become aware of our moral obligations when we ask what any reasonable person
must admit is the right thing to do in this situation. Pure practical
rationality distinguishes itself from pure practical rationality by its general
principles or maxims being traced back not to some specific inclination or
desire but rather to one's own rational awareness of one's duty as such. The
will of the moral individual is therefore "autonomous," since the
good will is not determined by anything outside itself, making it in the
fullest sense "free."
Kant's theory of morality is based on the concept of "imperatives,"
which are commands that dictate what we must do to achieve certain ends. He
formulates the categorical imperative as follows: "Act only according to
that maxim that you can at the same time thereby will that it become a universal
law." He emphasizes the need for a single categorical imperative, but
offers four alternative formulations. The first formulation states that one
should act as if the maximum of their action should become through their will a
natural law, expresses the lawfulness and universality of the good will as pure
practical reason. The second formulation states that one should treat humanity,
both in one's own person and in the person of every other, as an end and never
merely as a means. The third formulation explicitly draws on this notion of
autonomy: "Act in such a way that the will can view itself in its maxim as
at the same making a universal law." Finally, the fourth formulation
brings together the notions of universality and the notion of human beings as
ends in themselves.
Kant's critique of practical reason addresses the ontological implications of
his new theory, focusing on the question of freedom and how it can be
reconciled with the idea of natural causality. He asserts that freedom is the
cornerstone of a system of pure, even speculative reason, and that all other
concepts, such as God and immortality, follow from freedom and receive content
and objective reality through it.
Kant believes that the Stoics fail to appreciate actual human psychology if
they believe that we can (or should) extinguish any hopes for material
happiness and well-being in this life. He believes that the only thing that can
be said to be good without qualification is a good will, but we can envisage a
more comprehensive good that would entail a coincidence between happiness and
moral worth.
Kant's metaphysical grounds of a doctrine of virtue focus on things we cannot
know or count on, but that a moral person must hope for when acting in
conformity with the moral law. He emphasizes that this resolve is always in
danger and must be constantly and consistently renewed because human motivation
never eliminates heteronomous inclinations that even the smallest moral resolve
cannot completely extinguish.
Kant's philosophical reflections on judgments of taste have significant
implications for theories of art, artistic creativity, and philosophical
determinations of concepts such as beauty and sublimity. His Critique of
Judgment from 1790 examines the nature of these judgments and the validity of
various teleological claims. Aesthetic judgments are subjective and dependent
on individual sensibilities and preferences, while moral claims are based on
pure practical reason and absolute obligation.
Judgments of taste, specifically judgments about what is and is not beautiful,
resemble moral claims and theoretical claims about truth in that they claim
universal assent even without an objective basis. They share the characteristic
that they seem to be made from the standpoint of an impartial observer, as one
can judge an object beautiful without necessarily having an interest in
possessing that object. The feeling of pleasure (lust) awakens in the person
who experiences the object, and Kant concludes that it must be something about
the experiencing of the object that gives rise to the judgment.
In his analysis of the beautiful, Kant focuses on the concept of the sublime,
which he believes is a transcendent object beyond our grasp. Experiences of the
sublime serve as symbols of transcendent objects that lie beyond our intellect,
helping to foster an appropriate sensitivity to nonnatural objects such as duty
and human beings as persons. Prime examples of the sublime are overwhelming
natural phenomena like the vastness of the sea, the majesty of mountains, or
the ferocity of a storm.
Kant develops a theory of genius in the Critique of Judgment, which has been
influential not only in philosophical aesthetics but also in the
self-understanding of many artists in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.
Beauty is not simply a matter of the intellect, and there are no rules for what
makes an article beautiful or not.
Kant's philosophy of right has been a subject of significant debate and
analysis, with his metaphysics of morals receiving more attention. He posits
that "persons" are entities who possess practical reason that makes
them morally accountable and endows them with rights. In a state of nature,
only physical goods, including one's own bodily well-being, can be reliably
secured only if there is an enforcement mechanism that makes it in everyone's
self-interest to observe the rights of others, namely a civil society with
recognized laws and institutions that enforce them.
Tuesday, 4 June 2024
Thomas Nenon, "Immanuel Kant’s Turn to Transcendental Philosophy" (Summary)
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Raymond Williams, "Modern Tragedy" (Book Note)
Raymond Williams’s Modern Tragedy offers a nuanced re-evaluation of the concept of tragedy by moving beyond classical definitions and situa...
-
The feminist economics project has made significant strides. This progress is particularly notable as feminist economics has transitioned ...
-
Armstrong's theory of the novel is distinct from Watt's, as she places greater emphasis on the history of female subjectivity and ...
-
The Process of Recording and Consumption • The process of recording and consumption is akin to the production of production, with the produ...
No comments:
Post a Comment