Kant's philosophy of reason is marked by a unique fate, as
it is burdened with questions that it cannot ignore but cannot answer. These
questions, such as freedom, immortality, and God, arise in human experience and
reflection but exceed the capacity of reason to determine cognitively. Kant
believes that cognition is restricted to mundane phenomena and the necessary
laws governing their operation. However, Kant opens another door to the
metaphysical issues of God, freedom, and immortality through practical reason,
freedom, and faith.
Kant's critical philosophy denies knowledge to make room for faith, practical
faith, and freedom. Practical faith and freedom are important, but this access
is for practical purposes only and is not theoretical knowledge of any
supersensible object(s). In determining the bounds of cognition and proscribing
any cognitive transcendence of such boundaries, Kant raises a paradox: if one
knows they are free, they must know themselves as a conditioned phenomenal
object subject to causal mechanical necessity. This paradox leads to Kant
applying his doctrine of denial of knowledge to make room for faith and
distinguishing between appearances (phenomena) and things in themselves
(noumena).
In terms of self-consciousness of freedom, Kant argues that there is no
cognitive access of the self to its freedom. Instead, the consciousness of
freedom is mediated by the moral law, which is the ratio cognoscendi of freedom
and freedom is the ratio essendi of the moral law. This means that only a being
who is free is capable of apprehending a moral imperative and the moral law.
Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, a student and translator of David Hume, was a
prominent critic of Kant and German idealism. He believed that reason and
philosophical cognition are self-subverting, leading to a disastrous choice
between false reason and no reason at all. Jacobi's doctrine of immediate
knowing or Gefühlsphilosophie offers a mixture of Humean impressions and Kant's
practical faith, conceiving faith as an immediate certainty that excludes all
proofs absolutely and is simply the representation agreeing with the thing
being represented.
Friedrich Heinrich Fichte, a German philosopher, argued that the mediation of
the self to itself by the other becomes a major problem in the development and
transformation of idealism into a philosophy of spirit. He proposed an
alternative explanation to the problem of knowing that one is free: freedom is
intersubjectively mediated. Fichte insists that the human being (and so all
finite beings generally) becomes human only among others. The relation of free
beings to each other is therefore a relation of reciprocity through
intelligence and freedom.
Husserl's transcendental phenomenology is a science of the life-world, not to be
confused with the mundane natural science of empirical psychology. His
transcendental method focuses on subjective meaning-bestowal and the
ontological sense of the primordial life-world, which he critiques in his
critique of science. Husserl's transcendental idealism asserts that the
transcendental subject takes priority over the sense(s) it constitutes, while
ordinary consciousness asserts that relations of self and world are inherently
two-sided and reciprocal.
Husserl's account of intersubjectivity in the fourth Cartesian Meditation
generates two opposing requirements: (i) all sense is constituted by the
transcendental ego as part of its self-explication, and (ii) the other must be
constituted as other. In ordinary life-world experience, one person is just as
"real" as another; each is self-presence and presenting and not
reducible to a representation.
The reflective turn of transcendental phenomenology commits Husserl to a
firstperson account, with only one being the "primordial I" and all
the rest being "others." This implies a fundamental asymmetry between
the primordial I and the other, as the other as constituted is not
self-presenting or self-manifesting. Husserl accounts for intersubjectivity
through the concepts of pairing and appresentation, which is an analogical
transfer of sense.
Husserl denies that appresentation is an inference or argument from analogy,
blurring the distinction between the human ego and transcendental ego by
equivocation. The problem in Husserl's account is that only one ego, the
primordial ego, is presented, and all others are appresented, which appears to
mean a derivative mode of presence.
The asymmetry between primordial ego and alter ego seems to undermine the
reciprocity insisted on by ordinary consciousness. Interpreters like Paul
Ricoeur argue that one must renounce the asymmetry of the relationship me-other
required by Husserl's monadic idealism to account for the reciprocity and
equalization required by empirical and sociological realism.
Fichte's work aims to provide a comprehensive and systematic presentation of
the relationship between ordinary consciousness and transcendental philosophy.
He posits that transcendental philosophy does not create anything but observes
an actual I, which embodies this system of thinking described by transcendental
philosophy. Fichte's reformulation of the transcendental viewpoint posits that
there is nothing outside of reason, which is compatible with the ordinary
consciousness thesis that there are persons. However, the question of what the
spatial term "outside" means and whether it is appropriate in
transcendental philosophy remains an ambiguity.
Fichte's phenomenological descriptions of ordinary consciousness and the
experience of being summoned to freedom are discussed in his Lectures
Concerning the Vocation of the Scholar and the face of the other, which
anticipates Levinas's discussion in Totality and Infinitity. Both agree that
the face has broad ethically obligating significance, summoning the individual
to responsible freedom.
In his Grundlage des Naturrechts, Fichte addresses the issue of
intersubjectivity in philosophy, focusing on how consciousness transcends
itself. He proposes the concept of the Auff orderung by other, which contrasts
the transcendental-speculative perspective and the ordinary consciousness
perspective. The Auff orderung is based on the idea that the other person, the
summoner, takes priority over the one summoned.
From the transcendental perspective, freedom is described negatively as not
being determined, but as transcendental, pure freedom is radically
indeterminate and has the power to determine itself out of this radical
indeterminacy. Transcendental analysis emphasizes the importance of
self-generating responses to others, even if they refuse the summons.
In Naturrecht, Fichte claims that freedom has a divided ground, partly external
to the subject (the "real ground") and partly internal to the subject
(the "ideal ground), implying an intersubjective mediation of freedom. In
conclusion, Fichte's approach to the issue of intersubjectivity in philosophy
is based on the idea that freedom is mediated, with the ground of action lying
immediately in the being outside of it and in the subject itself.
Fichte's philosophical work rejects the notion of correlation between ideal and
real grounds, arguing that it implies an inadequate conception of the unity of
the I. Instead, he believes that the I must be grasped as the unity of
synthesis and analysis, rather than a given. He emphasizes that separation occurs
in and through the unification, and unity occurs through the separation.
Fichte maintains the primacy of the will over the apparent
"externality" of the Auff orderung, demoting it to the status of a
phenomenon. This obscures his own important discovery of the Auff orderung,
which is that autonomy is mediated and achieved in union with other. The unity
of the I, supposed to be a unity of self and other, of synthesis and analysis,
turns out to be a subjective unity.
Fichte acknowledges a problem at this crucial step of his argument: the concept
of a summons is not the concept of the summons, but rather an act of willing.
From the transcendental standpoint, the move from willing oneself as a moral
agent to the summons implies that the real ground of freedom collapses into the
ideal, short-circuiting mediation. The I summons itself.
Fichte asserts that there is nothing outside of me, no alleged thing in itself
can be the object of my consciousness. For reason, there is no limitation by
others; all limitation is self-limitation, otherwise we have dogmatism. The
original limitation of the will, or practical reason, is expressed by the
categorical imperative, which sets for the will a moral task. According to
Fichte, the categorical imperative or self- summons is only a first step in
self-limitation, as it lacks determinacy and a determinate goal.
Fichte's compromise term, "community-mass," is grounded in
transcendental intersubjectivity and reciprocity. He argues that rational
beings are thought of and projected into the world of appearances to explain
them to oneself, contradicting his earlier claim that there is a community of
rational beings conditioning self-individuation.
Fichte maintains that individuation through the categorical imperative is only
a first step toward individuation, as the self-imposed categorical imperative
remains indeterminate. The transcendental analysis of moral individuation as
indeterminate points to the necessity of a complementary Auff orderung for its
determinacy and actualization in the sensible world.
Thursday, 6 June 2024
R R Williams, "Fichte and Husserl: Life-world, the Other, and Philosophi...
Wednesday, 5 June 2024
Raymond Williams, 10. Hegemony (Marxism and Literature)
The traditional definition of 'hegemony' is political rule
or domination, especially in relations between states. Marxism extended this
definition to relations between social classes and definitions of a ruling
class. Antonio Gramsci's work on the concept of 'hegemony' gained significant
meaning in his work, which distinguishes between 'rule' (dominia) and
'hegemony'. He differentiates between 'rule' as directly political forms and
'hegemony' as the complex interlocking of political, social, and cultural
forces.
The concept of 'hegemony' goes beyond 'culture' in its insistence on relating
the 'whole social process' to specific distributions of power and influence. In
any actual society, there are specific inequalities in means and capacity to
realize this process, primarily between classes. Gramsci introduced the
necessary recognition of dominance and subordination in what has still to be
recognized as a whole process.
The concept of 'hegemony' goes beyond 'ideology', as it is decisive not only
the conscious system of ideas and beliefs but also the whole lived social
process as practically organized by specific and dominant meanings and values.
Ideology, in its normal senses, is a relatively formal and articulated system
of meanings, values, and beliefs that can be abstracted as a 'worldview' or a
'class outlook'. This explains its popularity as a concept in retrospective
analysis (in base-superstructure models or homology), since a system of ideas
can be abstracted from that once living social process and represented as the
decisive form in which consciousness was at once expressed and controlled.
Ideology is recognizable as fully articulate and systematic forms, and there is
a tendency in the analysis of art to look only for similarly fully articulated
and systematic expressions of this ideology in the content
(base-superstructure) or form (homology) of actual works. In less selective
procedures, less dependent on the inherent classicism of the definition of form
as fully articulate and systematic, the tendency is to consider works as
variants of, or as variably affected by, the decisive abstracted ideology.
The concept of 'hegemony' often resembles these definitions but is distinct in
its refusal to equate consciousness with the articulate formal system which can
be and ordinarily be abstracted as 'ideology'. It does not exclude the
articulate and formal meanings, values, and beliefs that a dominant class
develops and propagates but does not equate them with consciousness. Instead,
it sees the relations of domination and subordination as a saturation of the
whole process of living, not only of political and economic activity but also
of the whole substance of lived identities and relationships.
Hegemony is not only the articulate upper level of 'ideology', nor are its
forms of control only those ordinarily seen as'manipulation' or
'indoctrination'. It is a whole body of practices and expectations over the
whole of living, including our senses, assignments of energy, shaping
perceptions of ourselves and the world. It constitutes a sense of reality for
most people in society, a sense of absolute because experienced reality beyond
which it is very difficult for most members of society to move in most areas of
their lives.
The concept of hegemony offers two immediate advantages: first, its forms of
domination and subordination correspond more closely to the normal processes of
social organization and control in developed societies than the more familiar
projections from the idea of a ruling class. This can speak to the realities of
electoral democracy, leisure, and private life more specifically and actively
than older ideas of domination. If the pressures and limits of a given form of
domination are experienced and internalized, the whole question of class rule
and opposition to it is transformed. Gramsci's emphasis on the creation of an
alternative hegemony leads to a much more profound and active sense of
revolutionary activity in a highly developed society than the persistently
abstract models derived from very different historical situations.
Second, there is a whole different way of seeing cultural activity, both as
tradition and practice. Cultural work and activity are not in any ordinary
sense a superstructure but are seen as more than superstructural expressions of
a formed social and economic structure. They are among the basic processes of
the formation itself and related to a much wider area of reality than the
abstractions of'social' and 'economic' experience. People see themselves and
each other in directly personal relationships, seeing the natural world and
themselves in it, and using their physical and material resources for what one
kind of society specializes to 'leisure', 'entertainment', and 'art'.
Many difficulties arise, both theoretically and practically, but it is
important to recognize how many blind alleys we may now be saved from entering.
If any lived culture is necessarily so extensive, the problems of domination
and subordination on the one hand and the extraordinary complexity of any
actual cultural tradition and practice on the other can at last be directly
approached. However, there is a closely related problem within the concept of
'hegemony' itself. In some uses, the totalizing tendency of the concept is
converted into an abstract totalization, which is readily compatible with
sophisticated senses of 'the superstructure' or even 'ideology'. The hegemony
can be seen as more uniform, more static, and more abstract than in practice,
if it is really understood.
The concept of hegemony is a complex and dynamic concept that encompasses both
the active and passive aspects of political and cultural processes. It is not
just a form of dominance, but a system or structure with specific and changing
pressures and limits. Hegemony is not just passively existing as a form of
dominance, but it is continually renewed, recreated, defended, and modified. It
is also constantly resisted by pressures not at all its own.
One way to express the distinction between practical and abstract senses within
the concept is to speak of 'the hegemonic' rather than 'hegemony' and 'the
dominant' rather than simple 'domination'. The reality of any hegemony is that
it is never either total or exclusive. At any time, forms of alternative or
directly oppositional politics and culture exist as significant elements in
society. Their active presence is decisive, not only because they have to be
included in any historical analysis but as forms which have had significant
effect on the hegemonic process itself.
A static hegemony, indicated by abstract totalizing definitions of a dominant
ideology or world-view, can ignore or isolate such alternatives and opposition.
However, the decisive hegemonic function is to control, transform, or even
incorporate them. In this active process, the hegemonic has to be seen as more
than the simple transmission of an (unchanging) dominance. Any hegemonic
process must be especially alert and responsive to the alternatives and
opposition which question or threaten its dominance.
Works of art, by their substantial and general character, are often especially
important as sources of this complex evidence. The major theoretical problem
with immediate effect on methods of analysis is to distinguish between
alternative and oppositional initiatives and contributions made within or
against a specific hegemony (which then sets certain limits to them or can
succeed in neutralizing, changing, or actually incorporating them) and other
kinds of initiative and contribution which are irreducible to the terms of the
original or adaptive hegemony and are in that sense independent.
Cultural process must not be assumed to be merely adaptive, extensive, and
incorporative. Authentic breaks within and beyond it, in specific social
conditions, have often occurred. By developing modes of analysis that can
discern the finite but significant openness of many actual initiatives and
contributions, we can better understand the persistent pressures and limits of
the hegemonic.
Tuesday, 4 June 2024
Thomas Nenon, "Immanuel Kant’s Turn to Transcendental Philosophy" (Summary)
Kant's work in 1781 marked a significant turning point in
the history of philosophy. His first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason
introduced a "critical" philosophy with a radical new approach to
traditional questions in epistemology and metaphysics, completely reshaping the
philosophical landscape. He would produce significant and original
contributions to philosophical ethics in his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of
Morals (1785), Critique of Practical Reason (1788), and the second part of his
Metaphysics of Morals (1797).
Kant's early works are commonly referred to as "precritical
writings," which give little hint of the scope, originality, and
significance of the work that followed. Born into a modest atmosphere
influenced by Pietism, Kant was strongly influenced by theology professor Franz
Albert Schultz and philosophy professor Martin Knutzen, who took seriously the
work of Leibnizian Christian Wolff. Other prominent influences included
Aristotelian philosophy and Christian Thomasius's eclecticism.
Kant's earliest publications deal with questions at the intersection of natural
science and philosophy and on methodological issues in philosophy and theology.
His first book, Th oughts on the True Estimation of Living Force, written in
1746 and published in 1749 when Kant was still a young student, and his
dissertation Succinct Exposition of Some Meditations on Fire and his General
History of Nature and Theory of the Heavens from the same year are examples of
the former. Prime examples of the latter include his 1755 essay A New
Exposition of the First Principles of Metaphysical Knowledge, his essay on The
Only Possible Basis of a Demonstration of the Existence of God, his
Investigations of the Clarity of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morals,
and the inaugural dissertation On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and
the Intelligible World, which he defended in conjunction with his appointment
to the rank of professor in 1770.
Much of the Critique hinges on Kant's analysis of the notion of
"experience" itself. He tries to show that experience involves more
than just having sense impressions, and that positive knowledge is possible
only on the basis of experience, which necessarily involves both sense
experience (intuitions) and the operations of the intellect (concepts). Kant
distinguishes between those functions of the mind involved in the organization
and unification of intuitions into knowledge from the functions that involve
the higher-order unifying operations of seeking overarching unities or ultimate
grounds for knowledge in objects that lie outside the realm of sense
experience.
Kant's primary focus is on reason only in its theoretical function, that is, in
its claims to knowledge. He concludes that the intellect in conjunction with
the senses can provide us with more or less reliable, empirical knowledge of
sense objects, but that reason alone cannot yield theoretical knowledge.
Kant's philosophy emphasizes the importance of understanding the categories of
thought and the role of concepts in recognizing and organizing the material
provided by intuition. He presents twelve categories of thinking that
correspond to the forms of judgment: quantity (universal, particular, or
individual), quality (reality, negation, limitation), relation (inherence and
substance, cause and effect, mutual interaction), and modality (possibility,
actuality, necessity). These categories are called the "metaphysical
deduction" of the categories and are necessary conditions for the
possibilities of experience and any object of experience for us.
Kant argues that experience, objects of experience, and even the consciousness
of the subjects who experience objects are unities, not just aggregates of data
that come and go over time. Each of these categories has a fundamental unity
across time in spite of the specific changes in the state of experience, in
objects, and in the subjects of experience over time. Knowledge involves
recognition of patterns and the assumption that there are patterns within
experience. The fact that we must assume that we can and do organize our
intuitions according to these patterns for knowledge to be possible is the core
insight that Kant advances in these sections.
However, the general arguments about the nature and necessity of the categories
leave open the question of how specific they apply to objects. Kant's
philosophy and approach to understanding nature involve identifying three
categories of relation: substance, causality, and modality. The categories of
relation have temporal schemata, such as simultaneity according to substance
and succession according to causality. Modality is characterized by its
relationship to the conditions of experience, such as possibility, actuality,
and necessity.
Attaining knowledge involves organizing the material provided by the senses
according to the general rules of what things are "always" given
together or "always" succeed each other. Intuition provides not only
the raw material for knowledge but also a guide for how to arrange them in terms
of their formal temporal relationships and the measure and corrective of
empirical knowledge through what Kant calls the "further course of
experience." Empirical knowledge is always open to revision because the
rules that we are attempting to discern through the course of specific
experiences given to us are intended as holding "always."
Kant's philosophy has been criticized for its close tie to modern natural
science, its focus on "objectivity," and its narrow notion of human
cognition. Subsequent developments in mathematics and natural science raise the
question whether Kant's orientation on Euclidean geometry and Newtonian physics
as paradigms of knowledge is evidence that his universal and unchangeable a
priori principles are actually assumptions that hold only relative to these
specific systems.
The Critique of Pure Reason by Augustus Kant is a philosophical treatise that
argues that philosophy can identify a priori, nonempirical, or
"metaphysical" principles for practical reason. Kant's moral theory
begins with an analysis of common intuitions about the nature of moral
obligation, asserting that there is nothing in the world that could be
considered good without any qualification except for a good will. He defines
"duty" as the necessity of an action done out of respect for the law.
Kant's answer to everyday common sense is that all of us experience cases where
our inclinations conflict with what we know we ought to do (our duty). We
become aware of our moral obligations when we ask what any reasonable person
must admit is the right thing to do in this situation. Pure practical
rationality distinguishes itself from pure practical rationality by its general
principles or maxims being traced back not to some specific inclination or
desire but rather to one's own rational awareness of one's duty as such. The
will of the moral individual is therefore "autonomous," since the
good will is not determined by anything outside itself, making it in the
fullest sense "free."
Kant's theory of morality is based on the concept of "imperatives,"
which are commands that dictate what we must do to achieve certain ends. He
formulates the categorical imperative as follows: "Act only according to
that maxim that you can at the same time thereby will that it become a universal
law." He emphasizes the need for a single categorical imperative, but
offers four alternative formulations. The first formulation states that one
should act as if the maximum of their action should become through their will a
natural law, expresses the lawfulness and universality of the good will as pure
practical reason. The second formulation states that one should treat humanity,
both in one's own person and in the person of every other, as an end and never
merely as a means. The third formulation explicitly draws on this notion of
autonomy: "Act in such a way that the will can view itself in its maxim as
at the same making a universal law." Finally, the fourth formulation
brings together the notions of universality and the notion of human beings as
ends in themselves.
Kant's critique of practical reason addresses the ontological implications of
his new theory, focusing on the question of freedom and how it can be
reconciled with the idea of natural causality. He asserts that freedom is the
cornerstone of a system of pure, even speculative reason, and that all other
concepts, such as God and immortality, follow from freedom and receive content
and objective reality through it.
Kant believes that the Stoics fail to appreciate actual human psychology if
they believe that we can (or should) extinguish any hopes for material
happiness and well-being in this life. He believes that the only thing that can
be said to be good without qualification is a good will, but we can envisage a
more comprehensive good that would entail a coincidence between happiness and
moral worth.
Kant's metaphysical grounds of a doctrine of virtue focus on things we cannot
know or count on, but that a moral person must hope for when acting in
conformity with the moral law. He emphasizes that this resolve is always in
danger and must be constantly and consistently renewed because human motivation
never eliminates heteronomous inclinations that even the smallest moral resolve
cannot completely extinguish.
Kant's philosophical reflections on judgments of taste have significant
implications for theories of art, artistic creativity, and philosophical
determinations of concepts such as beauty and sublimity. His Critique of
Judgment from 1790 examines the nature of these judgments and the validity of
various teleological claims. Aesthetic judgments are subjective and dependent
on individual sensibilities and preferences, while moral claims are based on
pure practical reason and absolute obligation.
Judgments of taste, specifically judgments about what is and is not beautiful,
resemble moral claims and theoretical claims about truth in that they claim
universal assent even without an objective basis. They share the characteristic
that they seem to be made from the standpoint of an impartial observer, as one
can judge an object beautiful without necessarily having an interest in
possessing that object. The feeling of pleasure (lust) awakens in the person
who experiences the object, and Kant concludes that it must be something about
the experiencing of the object that gives rise to the judgment.
In his analysis of the beautiful, Kant focuses on the concept of the sublime,
which he believes is a transcendent object beyond our grasp. Experiences of the
sublime serve as symbols of transcendent objects that lie beyond our intellect,
helping to foster an appropriate sensitivity to nonnatural objects such as duty
and human beings as persons. Prime examples of the sublime are overwhelming
natural phenomena like the vastness of the sea, the majesty of mountains, or
the ferocity of a storm.
Kant develops a theory of genius in the Critique of Judgment, which has been
influential not only in philosophical aesthetics but also in the
self-understanding of many artists in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.
Beauty is not simply a matter of the intellect, and there are no rules for what
makes an article beautiful or not.
Kant's philosophy of right has been a subject of significant debate and
analysis, with his metaphysics of morals receiving more attention. He posits
that "persons" are entities who possess practical reason that makes
them morally accountable and endows them with rights. In a state of nature,
only physical goods, including one's own bodily well-being, can be reliably
secured only if there is an enforcement mechanism that makes it in everyone's
self-interest to observe the rights of others, namely a civil society with
recognized laws and institutions that enforce them.
Aquinas and Ethics
Aquinas acknowledges
that humans have only one ultimate end, which is something that satisfies one's
desires. He maintains that there are objective truths about the nature of
happiness and that there are nearly an infinite number of ways to manifest
virtues in various professions. He also considers the expression "ultimate
end" or "happiness" to be ambiguous, distinguishing between the
happiness humans can possess in this life, which he calls "imperfect human
happiness," and the happiness possessed by God, angels, and the blessed,
which he considers perfect.
Aquinas' philosophy focuses on the nature of human happiness, which is the
pursuit of good or happiness through virtuous actions. He agrees with Aristotle
that the attainment of happiness involves the soul's activity expressing
virtue, particularly the best virtue of contemplation, where the object of such
contemplation is the best possible object, God. Aquinas believes that human
beings in this life, even those who possess the infused virtues, at best attain
happiness only imperfectly since their contemplation and love of God are, at
best, imperfect.
Aquinas is a moral perfectionist, meaning that the means to human happiness
come not by way of merely good human actions but by way of perfect or virtuous
moral actions. Morally virtuous human actions are actions that perfect the
human agent that performs them, leading to happiness for the agent that
performs them. He rejects the view that all bodily pleasures are evil, as it is
natural for human beings to experience bodily and sensitive pleasures in this
life.
Mortally virtuous action is more than just morally good action; it is a
combination of the kind of action, circumstances surrounding an action, and
motivation for action. It arises from a good moral habit or virtue that makes
it possible to act with moral excellence. However, one morally good action is
not necessarily a morally virtuous act, as virtuous actions arise from a habit
such that one wills to do what is virtuous with ease.
Aquinas' account of the means to happiness as moral virtues reveals two
different kinds of virtue: natural virtues, which are attainable through reason
and will, and supernatural virtues, which come only by grace. Aquinas believes
that humans can acquire virtues that perfect human beings according to their
natural end by repeatedly performing the kinds of acts a virtuous person
performs, or habituation. He calls these virtues human virtues, distinguishing
them from "infused" virtues, which are virtues we have only by way of
a gift from God, not by habituation.
Infused virtues are perfections of our natural powers that enable us to do
something well and easily. They differ from human virtues in several ways.
First, unlike human virtues, infused virtues enable us to perfect our powers so
that we can perform acts in this life commensurate with or as a means to
eternal life in heaven. Second, infused virtues are wholly gifts from God,
unlike human virtues.
Aquinas thinks that neither infused nor human virtue makes a human being impervious
to committing mortal sin. Mortal sins kill supernatural life in the soul,
making one fit for the supernatural reward of heaven. However, since infused
virtues are not acquired through habituation but are a function of being in a
state of grace as a free gift from God, just one mortal sin eliminates the
infused virtues in the soul. However, such mortal sins can be forgiven by God's
grace through the sacrament of penance, restoring a soul to the state of grace.
Aquinas posits that human virtues are perfections of the characteristically
human powers. He distinguishes between the rational powers of intellect and
will, which enable humans to think about actions in universal terms, and the
apprehensive powers of the soul, such as sense and intellect, and the
appetitive powers of the soul, which incline creatures towards a certain goal
or end based on how objects are apprehended by the senses and intellect.
Aquinas discusses five intellectual virtues: wisdom, understanding, science,
art, and prudence. Understanding involves the consideration of first
principles, while science is the intellectual ability to draw correct
conclusions from first principles within a particular subject domain. Art and
prudence are two intellectual virtues that bring about some practical effect.
Aquinas, a virtue ethicist, posits that there are two types of human virtues:
intellectual and moral. He distinguishes between perfect and imperfect human
moral virtues, where imperfect virtues are dispositions that one desires to do
good deeds well. In contrast, perfect virtues cannot be possessed apart from
one another, as they are dispositions that one is inclined to do good deeds in
the right way, at the right time, and for the proper motive.
Aquinas accepts the "unity of the virtues" thesis for two reasons.
First, he distinguishes virtues according to general properties of the virtues,
such as discretion belonging to prudence, rectitude to justice, moderation to
temperance, and strength of mind to courage. This way, he believes that one cannot
have any one of the perfect cardinal virtues without also possessing the
others. Second, he argues that one cannot be perfectly prudent unless they are
also perfectly temperate, just, and courageous. This is because a perfected
intellect is necessary for deciding on the virtuous thing to do in any given
situation. However, a perfect knowledge of the ends or principles of human
action requires the possession of virtues that perfect the irascible appetite,
concupiscible appetite, and will.
Aquinas also discusses moral knowledge, arguing that all humans who have
reached the age of reason and received an elementary moral education have a
kind of moral knowledge, namely, a knowledge of universal moral principles.
There are at least three types of universal principles of the natural law:
first principles (e.g., do good and avoid evil), second principles (e.g.,
honoring parents and gifts), and third principles (e.g., abstract formulations
of the commandments of the Decalogue).
To know the primary and secondary universal precepts of the natural law is to
have the human virtue of understanding with respect to the principles of moral
action. Moral knowledge of other sorts is built on the back of having the
virtue of understanding with respect to moral action. It is possible to have
the virtue of understanding without otherwise being morally virtuous, such as
prudentness and courage.
Aquinas believes that the proximate measure for the goodness and badness of
human actions is human reason, or right reason. However, right reason is also a
part of God's mind, making God the ultimate standard for moral goodness. He
uses the language of law to discuss God as the measure of morally good acts,
stating that God's infinite and perfect being is the ultimate rule or measure for
all creaturely activity, including normative activity.
Aquinas believes that none of the precepts of the Decalogue are dispensable, as
each of the Ten Commandments is a fundamental precept of the natural law.
However, it would be a contradiction for God to will that a fundamental precept
of the natural law be violated, as it would contradict God's own perfection.
Therefore, God's will and perfection are the same, and a contradiction in terms
would be necessary for living a good human life.
Monday, 3 June 2024
Carolyn Steedman's "Culture, Cultural Studies and the Historians" (Summary)
Carolyn Steedman’s
essay Culture, Cultural Studies and the Historians discusses the concept of
culture, cultural studies in Britain since the last war, and the connection
between these concepts to the practice and writing of history. Steedman follows
a historiographical tradition laid down by British cultural studies, which
usually organize themselves in a particular way, rendering up their own account
in terms of three key-texts: Richard Hoggart's The Uses of Literacy (1957),
Raymond Williams's Culture and Society (1958), and E. P. Thompson's The Making
of the English Working Class (1963).
Steedman argues that history is the most impermanent of written forms, as it is
only an account that will last a while. The practice of historical work, the
uncovering of new facts, and the endless reordering of the immense detail that
makes the historian's map of the past performs this act of narrative
destabilization daily. The written history is a story that can only be told by
the implicit understanding that things are not over, that the story isn't
finished, and can never be finished.
However, when text-based historical knowledge is removed from the narrative and
cognitive frame of historical practice and used within another field, it loses
its impermanence and potential irony. The historical item taken out of its
narrative setting to explain something else is stabilized, making it a building
block for a different structure of explanation. This has been observed in the
use of the written history within sociological explanation.
Steedman asserts that the first bourgeois individual was not an economic man
but a domestic woman, born of conduct books, educational manuals, and possibly
Samuel Richardson's pen.
She expresses concerns about the authenticity of Raymond Williams' account of
culture in Marxism and Literature and Keywords. They argue that Williams'
account may have been influenced by historical events, such as the sociology of
the gendered reader, family and childcare, and the influence of Locke's text.
They suggest that a program of reading and archive research could help identify
the historicized subjectivity in the feminine and explore Freud's theory of
human inwardness and interiority. The author believes that by 1995, the terms
'woman' and 'child' might be added to the schema, potentially leading to a more
profound change in the account. They also question whether there is a
connectedness to everything, suggesting that Williams may have never read Some
Thoughts Concerning Education, as the ideas expressed in the book would be
available from the historical air he breathed when writing about the late
seventeenth century.
Carolyn Porter discusses the underlying formalism of critical practice in
historical studies, focusing on the tendency of new historicists to use
"riveting anecdotes" to explore texts and contexts. This technique
reflects a principle of arbitrary connectedness, where any aspect of a society
is related to any other. Dominick LaCapra criticizes social historians for their
reliance on the concept of culture, where everything connects to everything
else and "culture" is the primordial reality in which all historical
actors have their being, do their thing, share discourses, worldviews, and
languages.
The social historian's reliance on the notion of "culture" as the
bottom line has its own history, as seen in the academy's elevation of
nineteenth-century historians like Burkhardt and de Tocqueville to canonical
status in the post-Second-World-War period. Cultural studies in Britain has intersected
with these questions, revealing a more general social and institutional shaping
of history and historical knowledge in Britain over the last thirty years.
Cultural studies in Britain is nervous about codifying methods of knowledge and
attempts at institutionalization, and is constantly repositioning subjects and
defining themselves through autobiography and oral history.
Cultural studies in the UK has evolved from native texts and was
institutionally established at the Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies in
Birmingham. However, the arrival of "structuralisms" disrupted this
evolution. The teaching and learning forms in cultural studies degrees have
been influenced by the culture concept in schools, which has played a role in
organizing historical knowledge for young children and adolescents. The
organization of historical knowledge in British cultural studies has been about
questions of education, accommodation to learners, and the allure of certain
teacher-student relationships.
The practice of history in university-based cultural studies began in the late
1960s, with the MA program at Birmingham. The center's Popular Memory Group
struggled with history's empiricism and resistance to theory. The educational
form within which they did their wrestling is inimical to conventional
historical practice, particularly archive research. Archive research is
expensive, time-consuming, and not practical for a group of people.
The textual approach used in these studies was inadequate, making no distinction
between spoken and written language, not acknowledging language as a form of
cognition and a process of development, and lacking strategies for analyzing
literary form as a negotiated form. The most urgent need for history is an
adequate model of both spoken and written language, and whether developed
within historical studies or by students of cultural studies working on the
past does not matter as much as the fact that it might be done.
The curriculum change in national education systems has been influenced by the
establishment of English literature as the foundation of a national system of
education between 1880 and 1920. This led to the reorganization of education in
terms of cheapness and practicality, with accessible texts being the primary
focus. However, the amount of history taught in British society has steadily
diminished over the last thirty years. The cheapness and practicality of
text-based historical inquiry can also be seen as a theoretical propriety. The
last great flowering of English progressive education in schools in the 1970s
was seen in both the English departments of secondary schools and the practice
of integrated topic work in many primary schools. This flowering was seen in
the breaking down of barriers between teachers and taught, common involvement
in a common project, and the use of texts to make enquirers of them all. The
practice of history in primary and lower forms of secondary schools has also
been influenced by pedagogical forms.
The focus of cultural studies has shifted from Masters teaching to
undergraduate degrees, with the need for historians to teach history. This
shift is due to the institutional setting, alignment of humanities subjects
under departmental reorganization in polytechnics, and the need for students to
understand the interface of different knowledges brought together in
undergraduate teaching. As a result, British cultural studies needs to consider
its approach to history and the kind of historical thinking it will ask its
students to perform.
In a dehistoricized intellectual world, all children in society will be taught
exactly the same set of historical knowledges from the age of five to sixteen.
British cultural studies may be able to achieve what history cannot, as the
history of pedagogical practice and educational forms puts cultural studies in
a position to do its own historiography. However, after conference days,
cultural studies must ask questions about why they want history, what new acts
of transference will items from the past help cultural studies perform, how it
will be done and taught, whether there will be room for detailed historical
work or rely on schematic and secondary sweeps through time.
Raymond Williams, 9. Typification and Homology (Marxism and Literature)
Sunday, 2 June 2024
Edward Soja's "History, Geography, Modernity" (Summary)
The nineteenth-century
obsession with history, as described by Foucault, has not fully been replaced
by a spatialization of thought and experience. An essentially historical
epistemology continues to pervade the critical consciousness of modern social
theory, understanding the world primarily through the dynamics arising from the
emplacement of social being and becoming in the interpretive contexts of time.
This enduring epistemological presence has preserved a privileged place for the
'historical imagination' in defining the nature of critical insight and
interpretation.
As we move closer to the end of the twentieth century, Foucault's premonitory
observations on the emergence of an 'epoch of space' assume a more reasonable
cast. The material and intellectual contexts of modern critical social theory
have begun to shift dramatically, with calls for a far-reaching spatialization
of the critical imagination. A distinctively postmodern and critical human
geography is taking shape, brashly reasserting the interpretive significance of
space in the historically privileged confines of contemporary critical thought.
New possibilities are being generated from this creative commingling, such as a
simultaneously historical and geographical materialism, a triple dialectic of
space, time, and social being, and a transformative re-theorization of the
relations between history, geography, and modernity.
Postmodern critical human geography emerged in the late 1960s, but was largely
ignored due to the reaffirmation of history over geography in Western Marxism
and liberal social science. C. Wright Mills's sociological imagination provides
a basis for spatializing the historical narrative and reinterpreting critical
social theory. Mills argues that the sociological imagination is rooted in
historical rationality, a concept that applies to critical social science and
Marxism. He argues that individuals can understand their own experiences and
fate by locating themselves within their period and becoming aware of the
chances of all individuals in their circumstances. The sociological imagination
enables us to grasp history and biography, and their relations within society.
Recognizing this task and promise is the mark of a classic social analyst.
The historical imagination, as described by Edward Soja, is a central aspect of
critical social theory. It reduces meaning and action to the temporal constitution
and experience of social being. This rationality is grounded in the
intersections of history, biography, and society, and is shared by all social
theories. The historical imagination is never completely spaceless, but it is
always time and history that provide the primary "variable
containers" in these geographies. Critical social theory has been
particularly central to the search for practical understanding of the world as
a means of emancipation versus maintenance of the status quo.
The development of critical social theory has revolved around the assertion of
a mutable history against perspectives and practices that mystify the
changeability of the world. The critical historical discourse sets itself
against abstract and transhistorical universalizations, naturalisms,
empiricals, positivisms, religious and ideological fatalisms, and any
conceptualizations of the world that freeze the frangibility of time, the
possibility of 'breaking' and remaking history.
Historicalism has been conventionally defined in several ways, including
neutral, deliberate, and hostile. However, this definition identifies
historicism as an overdeveloped historical contextualization of social life and
social theory that actively submerges and peripheralizes the geographical or
spatial imagination. This definition does not deny the extraordinary power and
importance of historiography as a mode of emancipatory insight but identifies
historicism with the creation of a critical silence, an implicit subordination
of space to time that obscures geographical interpretations of the
changeability of the social world.
Michel Foucault's contributions to critical human geography can be traced back
to his historical insights, particularly in his lectures and interviews. He
introduced the concept of 'heterotopias' as the characteristic spaces of the
modern world, moving away from the hierarchical 'ensemble of places' of the
Middle Ages and the enveloping'space of emplacement' opened up by Galileo.
Foucault emphasized the importance of an external space, the lived and socially
produced space of sites and their relations. These heterogeneous spaces are
constituted in every society but take varied forms and change over time. He
identified many such sites, such as the cemetery, church, theater, garden,
museum, library, fairground, barracks, prison, Moslem Hamam, Scandinavian
sauna, brothel, and colony. Foucault contrasts these'real places' with the
'fundamentally unreal spaces' of utopias, which present society in either a
perfected form or turned upside down. The heterotopia can juxtapose in a single
real place several incompatible spaces, either creating a space of illusion or
creating a space that is other, as perfect as ours is messy and
ill-constructed.
2
Foucault's work argues against historicism and prevailing treatments of space
in human sciences. He proposes a heterogeneous and relational space of
heterotopias, which is neither a substanceless void nor a repository of
physical forms. Foucault's innovative interpretation of space and time is
influenced by structuralism, a critical reorientation that connects space and
time in new and revealing ways. Structuralism aims to establish an ensemble of
relations that make elements appear juxtaposed, set off against one another.
This synchronic configuration is the spatialization of history, the making of
history entwined with the social production of space. Foucault's spatialization
of history was provocatively spatialized from the very start, opening up
history to an interpretative geography. He emphasizes the centrality of space
to the critical eye, especially regarding the contemporary moment. In an
interview, Foucault reminisces about his exploration of 'Of other spaces' and
the enraged reactions it engendered from those he once identified as the 'pious
descendants of time'. He believes that space is fundamental in any form of
communal life and any exercise of power.
Foucault's exploration of the "fatal intersection of time with space"
in his writings is a reflection of his post-historicist and postmodern critical
human geography. He was a historian who never abandoned his allegiance to the
master identity of modern critical thought. Foucault had to admit that
geography was always at the heart of his concerns, and this realization
appeared in an interview with the editors of the French journal of radical
geography, Herodote.
Foucault's argument takes a new turn, questioning the origins of the
devaluation of space that has prevailed for generations. He takes an
integrative rather than deconstructive path, holding onto his history but
adding the crucial nexus of the linkage between space, knowledge, and power.
For those who confuse history with the old schemas of evolution, living
continuity, organic development, the progress of consciousness, or the project
of existence, the use of spatial terms seems to have an air of an anti-history.
Foucault's spatializing description of discursive realities gives way to the
analysis of related effects of power. In 'The Eye of Power', he restates his
ecumenical project, stating that a whole history remains to be written of
spaces, which would also be the history of powers, from the great strategies of
geopolitics to the little tactics of the habitat. Foucault postpones a direct
critique of historicism with an acute lateral glance, maintaining his
spatializing project while preserving his historical stance.
Marshall Berman's book, All that Is Solid Melts into Air: The Experience of
Modernity, explores the reconfigurations of social life in capitalism over the
past four hundred years. He defines modernity as a mode of vital experience,
encompassing time, space, history, geography, sequence, and simultaneity.
Modernity is comprised of both context and conjuncture, reflecting the specific
and changing meanings of space, time, and being. Berman's work serves as a
means of reinforcing debates on history and geography in critical social theory
and defining the context and conjuncture of postmodernity. The spatial order of
human existence arises from the social production of space, while the temporal
order is concretized in the making of history. The social order of
being-in-the-world revolves around the constitution of society, the production
and reproduction of social relations, institutions, and practices.
The experience of modernity is shaped by the changing "culture of time and
space" that took place from around 1880 to the outbreak of World War I.
Technological innovations and independent cultural developments created new
modes of thinking about and experiencing time and space, leading to a
transformation of life and thought dimensions. This expanded fin de siècle saw
industrial capitalism survive its predicted demise through radical social and
spatial restructuring, intensifying production relations and divisions of labor.
An altered culture of time and space emerged, restructuring historical
geography and introducing ambitious new visions for the future. Both fin de
siècle periods resonate with transformative socio-spatial processes, with a
complex and conflictful dialogue between urgent socio-economic modernization
sparked by systemwide crises affecting contemporary capitalist societies and a
responsive cultural and political modernism aiming to make sense of material
changes and gain control over their future directions.
Modernization is a continuous process of societal restructuring that is
periodically accelerated to produce a significant recomposition of
space-time-being in their concrete forms. For the past four hundred years,
these dynamics have been predominantly capitalist, as has the nature and
experience of modernity during that time. Modernization is unevenly developed
across time and space, inscribes different historical geographies across
different regional social formations, and has become systematically synchronic,
affecting all predominantly capitalist societies simultaneously.
The last half of the twentieth century has followed a similar trajectory, with
a prolonged expansionary period after the Second World War and an ongoing,
crisis-filled era of attempted modernization and restructuring taking us toward
the next fin de siècle.
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak’s Death of a Discipline
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak’s Death of a Discipline is a provocative and theoretically dense intervention in the field of comparative lite...
-
Culture, fundamentally, is ordinary; it's the bedrock of every human society. Each society crafts its own customs, pursues its own aim...
-
The Prison-House of Language by Fredric Jameson, first published in 1972, is a critical examination of structuralism and Russian formalis...
-
In exploring the landscape of Cultural Studies and its theoretical foundations, it becomes imperative to embark on a journey through time—...